124 | Solo: How Time Travel Could and Should Work

Time! It doesn’t stop, psychological effects of being under lockdown notwithstanding. How we experience time depends on our situation, but time itself just marches forward. Unless, of course, it’s possible to travel to the past, as countless science-fiction scenarios have depicted. But does that really make sense? Couldn’t we then change the past, even so dramatically that our own existence would never have happened? In this solo podcast I talk about both the physics and fiction of time travel. I point out that it might be allowed by the laws of physics, and explain how that would work, but that we really don’t know. And I try to make sense of some of the less-sensible depictions of cinematic time travel. Coming up with a logical theory that could account for Back to the Future isn’t easy, but podcasting isn’t for the squeamish.

Support Mindscape on Patreon.

But wait, there’s more! I was contacted by Janna Levin, who we fondly remember from Episode 27. Janna moonlights as Chair and Director of Sciences at Pioneer Works, an institution dedicated to bringing together creative people in art and science. Like the rest of us, they’ve been looking for ways to offer more online content in these pandemic times, so we thought about ways to collaborate. Here’s what they came up with: artist Azikiwe Mohammed has created an animated video backdrop to this podcast episode. The visuals are trippy, colorful, and inspired by (without trying to directly illustrate) what I talk about in the episode. You can check out a brief write-up at the Pioneer Works site, or view the video directly below.

[accordion clicktoclose=”true”][accordion-item tag=”p” state=closed title=”Click to Show Episode Transcript”]Click above to close.

0:00:00 Sean Carroll: Hello, everyone, welcome to the Mindscape Podcast. I’m your host, Sean Carroll. And I wanted to tell you, those of you who have not already heard it, a little anecdote about one of the ways in which, in a very tiny manner, I have influenced popular culture myself. You may have heard of the movie Avengers: Endgame. You probably have heard of it, it’s the highest-grossing movie of all time. And in that movie, a prominent role is played by the idea of time travel. So, I’m not gonna give away any spoilers for the movie, but there was a previous movie, Infinity War, in which bad things happened, and the heroes in Endgame want to fix those bad things by going to the past. So, when you wanna have time travel in your movie, you have to make some choices about how it works.

0:00:42 SC: We haven’t seen time travel in the real world, so, there’s different theories of how it could possibly happen, and at one point, Paul Rudd, who’s the actor playing Scott Lang, aka Ant-Man, he and everyone else are talking about the ideas of time travel, and Paul Rudd says, “So you’re telling me that Back to the Future is just bullshit?’ And I was actually serving as a science advisor for Endgame. Many people did. I was not the only one, but I remember I was in the room with the writers, the directors, the producers, and we were talking about the idea of time travel, time being one of my areas of expertise, purportedly as a physicist, and I explained why I had bad feelings about Back to the Future, why I thought it was illogical and so forth. And so one of the people in the room said, “You’re telling me Back to the Future is just bullshit,” and I agreed, and so that line appeared in the movie, I think I helped that line come into existence in a very tiny way. And I think for the most part, Endgame did a good job at time travel, it was a little bit hazy on this idea of whether or not you can affect the past by going into it, but it was much more respectable and logical than something like Back to the Future would be.

0:01:50 SC: But you know, I always… It always bothered me a little bit, that line, because I have an attitude, a philosophy, of how you should approach being a science advisor on movies. It’s easy to get a bad reputation in Hollywood as a scientist if all you do is hear what they wanna do in the movie and say, “No, you can’t do that,” right? There are plenty of scientists who are very happy to join the writers and directors and tell them that they can’t do that, they don’t really need extra people doing that. So, my attitude is when you get a screenplay or a detailed outline that already exists and you’re the science advisor, your job is not to scold them or tell them why they’re wrong, or give them a bad grade, okay? Your job is to help them, your job is to serve the movie, tell the best, most interesting story you possibly can. And the way that I find is helpful to sort of mentally line yourself to that job, that responsibility, is to think of the screenplay as data, rather than as a theory. In other words, you’re not looking at the screenplay and going, “Uh, no, I don’t think that’s the way it would work, I don’t think that’s an accurate description of reality,” that’s a bad attitude to have to a screenplay. The screenplay is, “In this world, what actually did happen?”

0:03:06 SC: And so, a scientist who gets data, gets an experimental result and whose response is, “No, that can’t happen,” is not gonna get that far, right? Once you shift your mental orientation from explaining what can and cannot happen to “Oh, this is what happened, it’s now my job to come up with an explanation for it,” it frees your mind quite a bit, and it’s almost always possible to come up with explanations of how things can happen. So, in my mind, a movie that would be the greatest challenge to turn into something logical would be something like Back to the Future, and it’s sort of time travel… Let’s just say it was a little free-wheeling when it came to the logic of time travel, which is actually admitted by the writers of the movie, they know it, but it’s a much-beloved movie, it served its purposes, narratively, so something good must be going on. And of course, time travel stories are still very, very popular. Recently Ed Solomon tweeted, the following tweet: “Over the next few weeks, people will have a chance to watch an exquisitely-crafted, physics-bending, very important filmic meditation on the quandaries of time and space, and also the much anticipated Tenant.”

0:04:14 SC: The joke, of course, here is the Tenet is a much-anticipated movie by Christopher Nolan that was just released. I haven’t seen it, since it’s only in theaters and we’re in the middle of a pandemic, but I understand the time and space bending-ness is a big part of it. Ed Solomon is one of the screenwriters on another such movie, namely Bill & Ted Face the Music. Ed was also a screenwriter for the original Bill & Ted movies, and Bill & Ted, in a very different way, have time travel as crucial plot points. So, we’re not tired yet of time travel movies and time travel logic. It’s important to see how far we can go in figuring it out. Thus, this podcast, which will be a solo job, I’m not gonna talk to anyone else, I have my own things to say about time travel, and I wanna talk about what time travel would be like, how it could possibly work. What is the science behind it? What do general relativity and quantum mechanics have to say about it, but then also philosophically, what would it mean? What would it mean for issues of causality and predetermination and free will? And finally, what does it mean narratively? Why do time travel stories work? How can they work, how should do they work? What is the guide to either understanding time travel stories that already exist, or maybe going out there and writing your own time travel story.

0:05:31 SC: So, bringing all of these different issues together and all these considerations is just the most fun thing in the world, and it’s intellectually a guess, and that’s what Mindscape is all about. And as if that were not too much fun already, we’re doing something special with this solo episode of Mindscape. You might remember Janna Levin, who was the guest on the very successful Episode 27 of Mindscape, that was two years ago, almost. So Janna, in addition to being a working physicist at Columbia, she’s also the Chair and curator of Pioneer Works in Brooklyn. Pioneer Works is an event space and a cooperative space that brings together artists and scientists to do fun, interdisciplinary, interconnected things. Of course, spaces in the physical realm are hard to operate these days. We’re more and more virtual, so Pioneer Works has been doing more and more online things, and Janna suggested a collaboration where we take a podcast episode of Mindscape and make it visual, make a YouTube video, or some other kind of video, where we have visual art in the background while you’re listening to the Mindscape episode.

0:06:38 SC: So they recruited artist Azikiwe Muhammed, who is a New York City artist, who made these wonderful computer-generated backgrounds that sort of relate to what I’m talking about here in the podcast about time travel. So they’re little spacey, a little technological, a little imaginative, sometimes they’re literally about what I’m talking about; sometimes they’re a little bit more figurative. But it’s a fun way to experience the podcast in a slightly different vein. So, I urge you to check that out. You can go to the Pioneer Works website, pioneerworks.org/broadcast. You can find the video there, or I’ll put a specific link to it on The Mindscape Podcast website. If you don’t know, we have a website, preposterousuniverse.com/podcast. If you look for the link for this particular episode, we’ll link to the video, there. It’s a different way, it’s optional, you don’t have to do it, but I think it’s a fun little departure from our norm, and fun departures from the norm. That’s also what we’re all about here, so with that, let’s go.

[music]

0:07:52 SC: These days, we think of time travel as basically a genre, right? There’s millions of time travel stories and movies and TV shows and whatever, and there are tropes. We have certain things that we expect already when someone says, “Oh, it’s a time travel story.” So it’s interesting that time travel stories aren’t that ancient. They haven’t been around that long. Whenever I say that, I’m gonna stand by that statement, but whenever I say that people bring up exceptions, there certainly were stories a long time ago that, in one big way or another, could be classified as time travel stories, but let’s just say it this way: They weren’t that popular. If you can think of 12 time travel stories before the year 1850 or so, I’d be very, very impressed.

0:08:33 SC: Whereas in the middle of the 19th century, time travel stories started becoming really, really popular. Of course, HG Wells wrote The Time Machine in, I think, 1895, I think it was, and after that, it truly took off. But it was somewhere around those years, or maybe a little bit before, that people started really coming up with this idea that time is a place to which we could go. And I think that this idea just hadn’t been there before. Like there was the past, there was the future, but these weren’t places that we could go. And clearly, by the fact that The Time Machine was in 1895, this idea that time could be a place we could go isn’t due to Einstein or general relativity or space time or anything like that, those came along in 1905 or later, but something gave people the idea that we should think of space and time as kind of similar as locations in some sense. Some people have suggested it’s because we begin to build mechanical clocks and watches, and that might be true. I really don’t know. Someone could look into it.

0:09:40 SC: I do know one of the earliest sources that says that you should think of time and space as similar is actually in a long poem by Edgar Allan Poe. Near the end of his life, he wrote a very long poem called Eureka, where he explained all of his theories about cosmology and physics, and fans of the poem, there aren’t that many fans, it’s kind of a weird, difficult poem, so fans of the poem like to say that he pre-figured things like the Big Bang cosmology and black holes and things like that. I don’t know, I think that he was… He was serious, Poe really believed that these ideas he was putting forward, but they weren’t based on data or even scientific theories. You can always say things that vaguely resemble a later scientific discovery, but one thing he does say very clearly is space and duration are one. He states very, very clearly that we should think of intervals in space and durations in time as the same kind of thing, okay? And once you have that idea in mind, then time travel stories become a natural thing. Once that you have the idea that space, which is clearly full of places you can go, is kind of like time, well, then maybe time is a place that you can go also, either the past or the future.

0:11:00 SC: And again, it’s not quite space-time. Einstein comes along with special relativity around 1905. Even when Einstein invented special relativity, he didn’t use the word “space-time.” That was his old math professor, Hermann Minkowski, in 1908, who pointed out that you could really formulate special relativity in an especially elegant and compelling way by thinking of it in terms of space-time. Einstein’s original reaction to that was that it was just unnecessary mathematical formalism, which does sometimes happen in physics, but in this case, he was eventually quickly converted to the idea that space-time is a good way of thinking about it. He invented general relativity where space-time is curved, and that’s gonna be important for our story here.

0:11:40 SC: But my point right now is that you don’t need relativity to have this move where you start thinking about time as a location. Even if you are just Newtonian, even if you just had old-school classical mechanics where space and time are both individually absolute, it still remains the case, that in order to meet someone for coffee, you have to tell them both where you’re gonna meet them in space and when you’re gonna meet them in time. So there’s obviously a similarity there that has nothing to do with relativity. In fact, there’s this very old debate, which I’m not gonna go into great details here about now, but of presentism versus eternalism. These are two different ways of thinking about the nature of time. In presentism, what you say is that reality, what really exists, is the world at the present moment. Okay? So that’s why it’s called presentism. Nothing tricky about the nomenclature there. You think that there’s a three-dimensional reality with everything going on, that’s what actually exists. The past used to exist, but it doesn’t exist anymore, and the future will exist, but it doesn’t exist as such at this moment. Okay?

0:12:54 SC: Eternalism, by contrast, and by the way, as a footnote, it is very difficult to talk about these things using the English language. Natural languages are just not designed to talk about these deep ideas about space and time in a compelling way, so, you have to fumble around a little bit. But an eternalist will say that all moments are equally real. To an eternalist, there’s the past, the present, and the future, from the point of view of someone at any moment in the four-dimensional world, but all of the moments and all of the locations in that four-dimensional world are equally real. To an eternalist, different moments in time are really like different points in space. Like if you’re located here, if I’m located in Los Angeles, Chicago is very far away from me, but that doesn’t mean I don’t think it’s real. Okay? So someone who thinks that time and space are on equal footing very naturally treats different moments of time as equally real. Not real at the same time. The past and future do not exist now, but they exist, if that makes sense. This is where the language fails us a little bit.

0:14:04 SC: Sometimes, in the philosophy literature, these are associated with ideas called the A Theory of Time for presentism and the B Theory for eternalism. There’s a very bad philosophical tendency to make perfectly good words that actually convey meaning and replace them with labels that are completely meaningless. Decades after being introduced to these ideas, I can never remember which is the A Theory and which is the B Theory. But the A Theory is a theory where time is tensed, there is now, will, what is happening, what will happen, what did happen. The B Theory is thought of as tenseless, so, there just are things, they’re not happening, or it’s not that they will happen, so everything exists. Okay? So, I’m not going to go through which of these theories is correct, although it’s obviously eternalism. If you want more about these theories, you can check out the video I did for my Biggest Ideas in the Universe series, where I talk about time and the nature of time, and so I go into presentism versus eternalism.

0:15:03 SC: Now, once relativity comes along, when it does come along, in the early 1900s, it dealt a blow to presentism. Relativity… Let’s go a little bit into explaining what relativity says. There’s a way of teaching relativity where… There’s a special relativity. 1905, Einstein’s first idea. General relativity was 10 years later. Special relativity is the theory that says, “The speed of light is the same to everyone. The amount of time that will elapse on a clock depends on the way in which you travel through space-time,” things like that. And there’s a way of teaching special relativity that emphasizes length contraction and time dilation, and a whole bunch of things that I don’t think is the right way to think about it. To me, special relativity is all about not only does space-time exist, not only should we think of space and time as being melded together in this single four-dimensional space-time, but the structure of space-time is something different.

0:16:06 SC: In Newtonian classical mechanics, in Newtonian classical mechanics, space and time both exist and are separately absolute. And that’s fancy language, what it means when you get down and dirty about it, what does that mean, space is absolute, time is absolute? What it means is, here I am in my office and I can say, “‘Well, okay, it is 1:32 PM now,’ and I could ask, ‘What is going on on a planet orbiting Alpha Centauri right now at this moment, at 1:32 PM?'” That’s a perfectly sensible question in Newtonian mechanics, because the four-dimensional universe is uniquely sliced into moments of time. Everyone agrees: If it’s 1:32 here, what’s happening at 1:32 everywhere else?

0:16:55 SC: Special relativity comes along and says, “Space-time exists. There’s the four-dimensional space-time, but you shouldn’t imagine some absolute slicing of space-time into three-dimensional moments of time that we call space at any one moment of time.” What special relativity… What it really says is, “Think locally rather than globally. Just don’t even ask the question about what is happening in Alpha Centauri at the same time,” that’s not a sensible question to ask. What you can ask is, “What do clocks read? What do meter-sticks read,” or whatever, and they need not be the same to different people. What special relativity does is it replaces the idea of slicing space-time into moments of time with a rule that says you cannot move faster than the speed of light.

0:17:47 SC: Now, look, this is difficult, this is a weird thing because those two ideas, one idea is that you can slice space-time into moments of time, the other is you can’t go faster than the speed of light, they don’t even sound comparable. They sound like a different kind of idea, so how can one replace the other? The answer is, if you think visually, and this is where having an audio-only podcast is a handicap, sorry about that, but think about the idea of light cones. Many of you have seen light cones portrayed in little diagrams before, but even if you haven’t, let’s call an event a point in both space and time. So an event lasts for zero time. It’s like right here, at this location, at one particular moment in time, and the rule in special relativity is from that event, nothing can travel faster than the speed of light away from it. So if you imagine at that event, a flash bulb goes off, light starts getting emitted in all directions, and you say, “Could I run fast enough or hop in a rocket and go fast enough to catch up to the light?” No, you cannot do it.

0:18:55 SC: So, I can imagine the beams of light going in all directions in space, and they will also move toward the future, and that defines the light cone. If you imagine visually in your head sort of drawing two axes, a horizontal axis for space, a vertical axis for time, the beams of light would move out at some angle away from that point, that would be the light cone. So, in special relativity, your future is not every moment in front of this moment of time that is simultaneous throughout the universe; your future is what’s inside that light cone. Okay? Things that are outside the light cone, like what’s going on in Alpha Centauri at the moment that I would call now, that’s not in my past, present, or future, I shouldn’t think about it that way. It’s just a place I can’t reach. I would have to go faster than the speed of light to get to that moment. I don’t need to go a faster than speed of light to get to Alpha Centauri, but to get to Alpha Centauri at a certain moment that I call now, I would have to go faster than the speed of light, ’cause it would take me four years to get to Alpha Centauri moving slower than the speed of light or at the speed of light. Okay?

0:20:03 SC: So, the way that special relativity works is it says, “There’s no such thing as simultaneity for events that are separated in space.” Tor events that are literally at the same part of the universe, there, you could be simultaneous, you are allowed to synchronize your watches if you’re very, very close by, but once you get far away from each other, there’s just no such thing as the idea of two things happening at the same time. What you can ask is, are two events in each other’s light cones or not? If they’re in each other’s light cones, then one is in the past and one is in the future. But if they’re not, we say that they are space-like separated from each other. No signal moving at allowed speed slower than light can get from one event to another, if those two events are space-like separated. Things that can travel on real trajectories slower than the speed of light are said to move on time-like paths throughout the universe; things that are imaginary and hypothetically move faster than the speed of light are on space-like paths. Okay?

0:21:05 SC: So rather than dividing space-time up into these slices of constant time, special relativity says at every event, there is a future light cone where things that that event can influence in, and there’s a past-light cone where all the events that can possibly influence this other event are located, and then there’s this outside region, the space-like separated region. There’s no such thing as uniquely slicing the universe into moments of time. So you’ll be unsurprised to learn that relativity dealt a blow to presentism, right? There’s no way of saying what the present moment is in any unique way once special relativity comes along. Again, this is sometimes said as, “Observers moving at different velocities will choose to divide up space and time differently.” And there’s some truth to that, but that’s not the point. That’s sort of a down the road kind of implication of it. I can choose to divide space and time however I want in relativity. There’s sort of a natural way to do it if I’m moving at a constant velocity, and that natural way is different for observers moving at different constant velocities.

0:22:14 SC: But all the point I wanna get across here is just that special relativity really removes the idea that there’s something special about the present moment. The present moment where you are listening to this podcast cannot be uniquely extended across the universe. And therefore, once relativity comes along, it’s much more natural to speak of the four-dimensional block universe, as we sometimes call it, the eternalist presentation of both space and time together glued into this one thing called space-time.

0:22:47 SC: Now, notice that if time travel were possible, we haven’t gotten to time travel yet, but if time travel were possible, if you could travel to the past, then that’d be an even bigger blow to presentism. How can you go somewhere that doesn’t even exist? [chuckle] Time travel is predicated on the idea of eternalism, that the past, present, and future are all places you can go, in some sense. So therefore, from now on for the rest of this podcast, I’m gonna be assuming an eternalist view of space and time. We can treat all the moments in the history of the universe as equally real. There’s one that I happen to be experiencing at this moment as I am talking; there’s a different moment in my future that you are experiencing as you’re listening, but all those moments are equally real.

0:23:36 SC: Okay, so, a consequence of this, of this special relativity point of view, if you can only move slower than the speed of light, then if you move… If you, again, imagine, hypothetically, moving faster than the speed of light, we’re allowed to let our imaginations roam a little bit, what would that mean? What would it imply if I could travel faster than the speed of light? Well, if I travel faster than the speed of light, so I go one minute into the future and also four light years, so I’m moving faster than the speed of light, I’m traveling four light years in a minute, but to say that I am moving a minute into the future is a statement that implies that I’ve chosen some reference frame that is stretched across four light-years of space. And the whole point of special relativity is that I can choose different reference frames. So the upshot of this is that if I can move faster than the speed of light, I might call it I’m moving into the future but I’m moving very fast in space, but in someone else’s reference frame, they see me moving backward in time. To someone else’s frame of reference, they would say that I arrived at a moment in time before I left. Okay?

0:24:54 SC: This is just, again, if special relativity were correct, Einstein’s gonna update it to general relativity, but the lesson still remains pretty valid here, if special relativity is correct, then if you can move faster than the speed of light, that’s equivalent to moving backwards in time. It is moving backwards in time from someone’s point of view, okay? So if special relativity were correct, a warp drive would be a time machine. If you believe in special relativity and you believe that nevertheless, some day, we will build a spaceship that can go faster than the speed of light, that is equivalent to being able to travel into the past. And I want you to remember that because this is gonna happen, this is gonna become an important point down later in the podcast, once you realize that you can go faster than the speed of light, then you can build a time machine, if special relativity is correct.

0:25:46 SC: Now, that doesn’t mean, another footnote here, that something like in Star Trek or Star Wars where we can travel faster than the speed of light, why don’t they have time machines all over the place? I mean, Star Trek kinda does have time machines. Star Trek helps itself to time travel whenever it wants to and then forgets that it has the ability to do that. But one answer, given our philosophy of “the screenplay is the data, not the theory,” rather than just saying, “Well, they’re wrong, that’s not how it would be,” is it possible that there is a theory where you could have warp drive without the possibility of going backward in time? And the answer is yes. Namely, special relativity is not correct. It would have to be not correct in a pretty dramatic way. One of the pillars of special relativity is the idea that nobody moving at any particular inertial trajectory through space, in other words, no one who’s moving at a constant velocity, is superior to anybody else. There is no absolute reference frame with respect to which you can measure your velocity.

0:26:49 SC: Remember, the ether was an idea that they had circa 1900 where they could, they thought that they could, measure their velocity with respect to it. We no longer think that exists. But maybe we’re wrong, right? So if you want to believe that there could be something like warp drive, there can be Warp Factor 9, which lets you go much faster than the speed of light, but somehow doesn’t let you go backward in time, what you have to imagine that somehow, there is an absolute reference frame in the universe with respect to which you can measure your velocity. So when Jean-Luc says, “Go Warp Factor 9,” that’s with respect to some ether, some sort of modern souped-up version of the ether that you and I don’t know about, but they discovered some time before the 24th century. I’m not gonna go into any details about that, but you can always try your best to make it make sense after the fact.

0:27:41 SC: Now, remember here, when we talk about special relativity, that is in contrast with general relativity, special relativity came first. It’s the theory that the speed of light is the maximum, every inertial trajectory is equivalent. Space-time exists, but space-time is rigid. Space-time is a background, it has a geometry, but the geometry is flat, and in particular, there is no gravity. When general relativity comes along, and we’ll get there in a bit, but general relativity, 1915, 1916 says space-time not only exists, and it’s not only a mathematical convenience, but it’s not rigid; it’s dynamical. It can move, it can bend, it can warp, and those bendings and warpings are what you and I perceive as gravity, whether it’s the gravity here on Earth or the Earth moving around the sun or a black hole or the Big Bang or whatever. All of that are different manifestations of the curvature of space-time, okay. So we’re not getting there yet, but that’s what I mean by special relativity, there’s no gravity, there’s no curvature. Even though special relativity says there’s no unique absolute way to divide up space-time into space and time, it still takes space-time as given, as a flat, rigid background on which everything happens.

0:28:57 SC: One way of thinking about the conceptual change when you go from Newtonian absolute space and absolute time to special relativity is that special relativity distinguishes two things that were the same thing in Newtonian physics, namely universal time and personal time. Okay? So, in a Newtonian world, had Newton been right, if you and I synchronized our watches so they said the same time, so they were saying exactly what we thought they did and they were good watches, they did not tick at the wrong rate or whatever, then you and I could go our separate ways, we could walk off, and there would be a sensible answer to the question, “What time is it?” And I could measure it either on my watch or on your watch, and they would say the same thing. There is this universal time coordinate throughout the world in Newtonian physics, and it is what your personal clock measures.

0:29:53 SC: In special relativity, these two ideas of a coordinate that stretches throughout the universe, that helps you find yourself in space-time, and the duration that is measured by a clock or a watch you carry with you, become completely separate. It’s like in space… Again, everything in special relativity is just the motto, “Time is kind of like space,” or “Space-time is kind of like space suitably interpreted.” So, if you have two locations in space, two cities, you can say what is the distance between them. And most people will understand what you mean. There is a shortest distance path between those two cities, and you can say how long that shortest distance path is. But everyone also knows that when you actually travel between two cities, let’s say, by driving on roads, the distance you will traverse is not that shortest distance, because you’re not gonna go exactly in a straight line, that’s as the crow flies or whatever you wanna call it. You will have to make twists and turns, and so, the actual reading on your odometer will be longer than the shortest distance path.

0:31:01 SC: When it comes to space, that just makes perfect sense. Everyone agrees, right? So special relativity says time is also like that. Time is something that we can personally measure, or we can talk about this abstract notion of a coordinate. It’s not a universal given thing, but we can choose a coordinate on the universe that helps us find things. So for example, when we do cosmology, we know that there’s all this stuff in the universe, there are galaxies, and there’s dark matter, and there are photons, and the cosmic microwave background, and all this stuff has sort of a rest frame. If you forget, just for convenience about the matter and the dark matter, just look at the cosmic microwave background, you can move to a frame, or you could, in your mind, imagine a reference frame or a velocity with respect to which the cosmic microwave background looks the same in all directions.

0:31:56 SC: And then if you change to moving at a different velocity with respect to where you started, then the microwave background will be blue-shifted if you’re moving toward it and red-shifted when you’re moving away. There’s only one reference frame cosmologically, where there is no overall net blue shift to a red shift for the cosmic microwave background, so you can think of that as the rest frame of the universe. So when we talk about the universe being 13.8 billion years old or whatever, we mean as measured in that rest frame for the universe. But you personally don’t have to travel in that rest frame. You and I can move around, and this is what gives rise to the famous twin paradox in special relativity. A twin born here on Earth and another twin born at the same time, but one of them just stays here on Earth, doesn’t do anything, whereas the other twin goes out in a rocket ship near the speed of light and then comes back. And even though the two twins were born at the same time and they age at the same rate and they have clocks, et cetera, the twin that went out in the rocket ship and comes back will experience less time. This is how you can remember the difference between space and time in general relativity… Or in special relativity, sorry.

0:33:05 SC: Space is kind of like time, but the difference is that in space, the straight line path is the shortest distance path, any other path will be longer distance. Time is the other way around. In time, the straight line path is the longest time path, any other path where you zip around in your rocket ship close to the speed of light, you will experience less time. So there is a difference between time and space in relativity. Okay? So that’s the distinction between universal time that I might use to find things in the universe. “Oh, these two black holes merged at such-and-such a time and place in the universe” versus the personal time. Every one of us carries around a clock, either literally or figuratively, and those clocks will read slightly different amounts, depending on how we travel through the universe. I mean, this is, of course, the most trivial and certainly true notion of what we mean when we say time travel.

0:34:04 SC: There’s the old joke. You can time travel into the future, the old joke is, yesterday, I traveled a day into the future, it took me 24 hours, but here I am. So everyone asks you… Whenever anyone asks you, “Can I travel in time?”, well, if you wanna be a wise-ass, you can say, “Yes, you can travel into the future one second per second,” in fact, it’s kind of necessary that you do, the new wrinkle is that in special relativity, in some well-defined sense, you can get to the future faster. What we mean by that is, if you think of the future as defined by some universal time-keeping parameter, like the rest frame of the microwave background, you can experience less time, but getting into the future. So if you zip off of the speed of light or very close to it in a rocket ship and zip back, the universe can age by a thousand years and you’ve only aged by a week. And there’s no limit. You can go as far into the future in as little time as you want, if you have a sufficiently powerful rocket ship. Okay.

0:35:08 SC: So that’s the respectable physics. [chuckle] That is everything that we really do understand in special relativity about traveling in time, namely, you can travel to the future, just like you could have done in Newtonian mechanics. If anything, special relativity is a little bit more restrictive, because you can’t travel faster than the speed of light, whereas in Newtonian mechanics, you could.

0:35:31 SC: But at this point, this is when we have to sort of take a breath and say, like, “Wait a minute, what do we mean by all this traveling through time in the first place?” It was a joke and not an especially funny joke when I said I traveled it yesterday a day into the future, and it took me 24 hours, right? There’s something that’s not exactly in line with what I mean by traveling. And again, this is where our language fails us. This is where we just don’t have the vocabulary to talk about this stuff in a sensible way. When we travel through space, we can talk about the rate, the velocity, the speed with which we are traveling to space. “I’m moving in the car at 80 kilometers per hour.” Okay. That’s a sensible thing to say, we all know what it means, it’s with respect to the rest frame defined by the road, et cetera, et cetera. But so what we mean by traveling through space is that as time passes, our location in space changes. That’s what it means to travel through space.

0:36:32 SC: So, there’s no exactly analogous notion of traveling through time. Of course, as time passes, our location and time changes. That’s just trivial and obvious. And our personal rate of traveling through time can never be anything but one second per second. What could it possibly be? It could be different relative to other people, but there’s never… As much I wanna be nice to movies or whatever, like if you ever see a movie where someone is traveling near the speed of light or near a black hole and they look at their watch and it stopped or is moving really quickly or something like that, either way, that’s nonsense, because whatever is happening to their internal perceptions of the world is also happening to the watch, as far as physics is concerned. If they’ve just been given time-altering drugs, that’s a completely different thing.

0:37:25 SC: Nevertheless, having put all those caveats down, there is a sense, there’s a feeling that we have, that we travel through time. There’s actually two different ways of talking about it which are pretty equivalent, in fact, most people just give and take equally between them, namely, the idea that you move through time, or that time passes you by. Either time flows around you, or that you have this motion through time, make up your mind about which is actually happening. I did another podcast, I’m sure that you listened to, with Lera Boroditsky, about the language we use to deal with time and how we borrow all these spatial metaphors: Time is in front of us or behind us, and different people, depending on circumstances, think of the future as being in front or behind you, et cetera. Okay?

0:38:15 SC: If you are presentist, if you really did believe that only the present moment existed, then there is some reality to the idea of flowing through time. What you mean by you is you now. And of course, you now changes and evolves, this is how the presentists think. There is some innate umph to the flow of time with respect to which time is moving and pushing you and changing you. And that’s a very natural, intuitive way to think. Like I said, presentism isn’t the way that I would eventually think, but you can’t blame a presentist for thinking that way. This is how we grow up. Right? I exist now and I am changing as time passes. The way that the eternalist would say it is that, there is a you at each moment. So, the thing that is you is the collection of all of these you’s at different moments. There’s not some essence of you that is not only located in space but also at a particular time; there is the you that exists at January 1st, 2021 at noon, there is the you that exists January 1st, 2021 at 12:01, and the you at 12:02, and all the other times, an infinite number of times in the approximation where time itself is continuous, okay?

0:39:35 SC: These are separate things, separate beings, but they’re not independent. They’re separate, but they’re connected. They’re related by causal and psychological continuity. The you at 12:01 is not that different, I hope, unless something dramatic happens. The you at 12:01 is not that different from the you at noon or the you at 12:02. They’re a little bit different. If you let a lot of time pass, then the atoms that are in your body change, many of them, not all of them, but a lot of them do. Certainly, you accumulate memories, not to mention aches and pains as you grow to a certain age over your life. So, the you at age 50 is not the you at age 20. They’re related to each other, the eternalist would say in a very clear way, but they are two different things. And that’s a shift in perspective that eternalism asks of us that can be hard to catch on to, but once you do, it does help understand a lot of worrisome features of personal identity.

0:40:37 SC: Derek Parfit, the philosopher, wrote about transporter machines, the Star Trek transporter. You get beamed down to the location of the planet. As far as I know, the start track writers were ambiguous about whether or not when you get beamed down, do you send your actual atoms, do you disassociate a person atom by atom, send them down to the surface of the planet and then reassemble them, or whether somehow they disassemble all the atoms, keep in mind or store the information about how they were related to each other, and then use matter on the planet where they were beaming them down to to re-assemble the person somehow out of those new atoms? I think it’s the information that is sent down, I think that is the implication sometimes, but it’s never made perfectly clear.

0:41:25 SC: And so you can ask: Did you kill the person to put them in the transporter machine? Is that death? Is that just a whole new person down there on the planet? I think that from a certain sort of intuitive, naive way of thinking, that’s absolutely true. That’s a very natural thing to think. In fact, those of you who listen to my podcast on Mindscape with Seth MacFarlane, who has his TV show, The Orville, which is, in many ways, an homage to Star Trek, he very specifically did not have transporter machines, does not have transport machines on the world of the Orville, and that’s in part why. He said he didn’t wanna keep killing his characters over and over again.

0:42:03 SC: So I think that Parfit would say… Derek Parfit, when he wrote about this, he tried to make the point that that’s not killing the person. There is a person that is reconstructed from the transporter machine, but that person shares the continuity of memories and desires and personality of the person who is disassembled in the transporter machine, therefore, at least if you’re an eternalist and you think that any of this makes sense at all, it makes perfect sense to think of them as the same person. There is a discontinuity of where that person happened to be located in space when they got transported, but the continuity of psychology and memory makes them two different manifestations at different times and in different locations of space of the same entity, of the same person. There’s no sort of metaphysical soul that has to travel; it’s just the pattern of their atoms that makes them who they are, and it’s the same pattern if you have a functioning transporter machine.

0:43:03 SC: Now, this all sounds very science fiction-y because it is, but it’s very relevant to things like the many-worlds interpretation of quantum mechanics. This is not… We’re gonna talk about quantum mechanics a little bit, but anyone who’s been listening to the podcast for a while has heard me talk about many-worlds, and the idea of many-worlds is any time you measure a quantum mechanical system that is in a superposition, like an electron could be spinning clockwise or counter-clockwise, before you measure it, it’s a superposition of both, they’re both really there. Afterward, there are now two worlds, two copies of reality, one in which you measured the spin clockwise and the other one counter-clockwise. So there’s the question people often have, like, which one is you? Which one are you going to end up being? And if you follow this logic of personal identity from Parfit and elsewhere, you would say, “Well, there’s no one that is the you. These are two people, they both were you, but they are now two different people. They’re in two different worlds, they’re not interacting.” So there’s no answer to the question, “Which one do you become?”

0:44:09 SC: And the reason why I go on this little tangent is because these questions of personal identity, these questions of how we think about who we are, need to be updated when you go from manifest image, folk physics, the way that we grow up thinking about the world, to the slightly harder and more abstract notions that are given to us by modern physics. And that’s very relevant for travel through time. So I say relativity, and certainly, if you can have time travel, deals a blow to presentism. It suggests that eternalism is a better way of thinking about time and space, but you can’t deny that we feel, we have the impression, that we are moving through time, that we are aging, that we are experiencing things. There’s definitely some momentum or some feeling there. So, where does that come from? And this is, as Dan Dennett, who I had on the podcast, likes to say, this is the job of philosophy. The job of philosophy is to reconcile the scientific image of the world with the manifest image of the world. The scientific image says there’s just different moments of time, they all exist, different copies of you at every moment; the manifest image says, I am one person right here and right now, and I change through time.

0:45:23 SC: So, you can ask, “Why do I feel like time is flowing around me?” or “Why do I feel like I am moving through time?” It’s very, very closely related to the question of free will: “Why do I feel like I make choices and have an influence over the future? Why do causes precede effects in time?” Even though at the end of the day, I might wanna say, “Well, it’s all just the laws of physics. It’s not that I personally had the ability to do anything; I’m just a bunch of particles and forces obeying the laws of physics.” Why do I feel I can make choices, is very closely related to, why do I feel like I’m flowing through time? And if you want a more sophisticated answer to this question from the philosophical and neuroscience perspective, give another listen to the podcast I did with Jenann Ismael who wrote the book How Physics Makes us Free.

0:46:14 SC: But let me give you a little bit of an insight here, because it does… It’s an important thing to consider when we talk about why time travel bothers us. Why do we think that there are paradoxes in time travel, and are they necessary or not? The issue is that on the one hand, we have these impersonal laws of physics. It doesn’t really matter whether the laws of physics are deterministic or not, that’s a red herring people often get stuck in. What matters is not the laws of physics are deterministic or not deterministic; what matters is, are there laws of physics, [chuckle] and are we, human beings, purely physical creatures obeying those laws? That’s kind of what matters. And the question is, if we are, if we are just made of physical stuff obeying the laws of physics and the laws of physics are impersonal and governed by equations, whether or not they’re deterministic, how in the world can we reconcile that with our humanity and our feelings that we move through time and make choices and affect the future?

0:47:12 SC: This wouldn’t really have been a question in a presentist universe. If you’re Aristotle, you think of things, even if they’re physical, they’re teleological, they have goals. There’s a future orientation toward how we talk about how things take place as the universe unfolds in time from the present moment to the future. But then classical mechanics comes along, even before relativity. You all know the story, again, if you’ve been listening to the podcast, but Pierre-Simon Laplace points out that you can imagine a vast intelligence, which we now call Laplace’s demon, which, if it knew everything about the universe at one moment of time and had infinite calculation power and knowledge of the laws of physics, to that vast intelligence, the past and the future are as equally evident as the present is, because there is a pattern. It’s not directed toward the future or toward the past, but at every moment of time, the entire future and the entire past are determined by what’s going on right then. Again, this might not be true because quantum mechanics came along, et cetera, but that was the classical mechanics view of the world: The clockwork universe, Laplace’s demon. And in that picture, where are we gonna locate the flow of time in any sense? The past, present, and future aren’t different, if you’re Laplace’s demon.

0:48:39 SC: So, here’s the bad news: You are not Laplace’s demon [chuckle] or maybe that’s the good news, I don’t know. But it’s very, very true, you are not Laplace’s demon. And the reason why I have to sort of hammer this home a little bit is because I think that people don’t quite appreciate the extent to which you are not Laplace’s demon. Laplace has this thought experiment. You have in mind, I don’t know, a box of gas or some billiard balls on a billiard table and they’re banging into each other, and you’re like, “Well, I don’t have perfect information about what those bill balls are doing, where they’re located, or how they’re moving, and I don’t even have the calculation ability to figure out what would happen, but I can imagine extrapolating to being a little bit smarter and having a little bit more information, and then I could do it and I’d be Laplace’s demon,” right?

0:49:28 SC: So I really need to hammer home the idea that it is not that easy in extrapolation. Laplace’s demon is a thought experiment; it was never meant to represent a goal, that we should try to be Laplace’s demon. The number of things going on in a single human being, or even in a single insect, or something very, very tiny, is so enormously mind-bogglingly large, and the precision that you would need to understand what was going on in them is so absurdly high, that it’s just silly to even imagine you could be Laplace’s demon. The analogy I sometimes use is: Imagine that you can bench-press 150 pounds, and you think to yourself, “Maybe if I practice and I get really good, I’ll bench-press 200 or 250.” And you think to yourself, “I can thought experiment myself into imagining I could bench-press 500 pounds or 1000 pounds.” True, you could do that. But going from “I can see the billiard balls on the table,” to “I can imagine being Laplace’s demon” isn’t like that. It’s like saying, “I can bench press 150 pounds, so let me imagine that I could bench press the sun.” [chuckle] Like the sun in the sky, right?

0:50:41 SC: It’s just out of the realm of sensibility. It’s not physically impossible, but the sun is a different kind of thing. You can’t even push it, right? It’s not just that it’s too massive; it’s just a whole different world out there. And so you should not think that, “Well, you know, I’m not really Laplace’s demon, but maybe that’s a good approximation.” That’s not a good approximation to anything. What you are is a machine or a collection of physical stuff that possesses incomplete information about the world and tries to impose order on that world to try to make a kind of sense of it. If you go back to the podcast interview we did with Karl Friston where he has a particular free energy principle. He thinks of the brain as being some kind of Bayesian reasoner that tries to understand what’s going on in the world and minimize surprise, okay?

0:51:31 SC: And that’s kind of what we try to do, and we’re pretty good at it, but when you dig into the actual things going on in our brains, it’s kind of amazing. It’s very, very different than Laplace’s demon, let’s put it that way. We both, in some very, very true sense, live in the past while constantly anticipating the future. What I mean by living in the past is you think that you are right now, you’re looking around you, you can see things, you can hear things, you can sense them with your fingers and your taste and smell and whatever, and you say, “I have an understanding or an image of what the world is right now.” But if you think about it, it takes time for your brain to put that image together. I mean, of course, it takes time for the light to get to you from what you’re looking at to your eyeballs, and then the neurological signal to get from your eyeball to your visual cortex. Likewise for sounds, and so forth. It takes some time for your brain to knit that all together into a coherent picture. And depending on what aspect you’re talking about, neuroscientists can actually pinpoint how much of a gap there is between what is literally happy now in the present moment and what you are perceiving as the moment of now. It’s measured in milliseconds. Tens of milliseconds, depending on exactly what we’re talking about. There are different time scales relevant to different phenomena.

0:53:00 SC: But you can see this, for example, my favorite demonstration is someone standing next to you and they’re dribbling a basketball. And so you see them dribbling, but you also hear the slap that the ball makes on the ground when it hits the ground. And your brain ties them together. You know that the visual image of the basketball hitting the ground gets to your eye a little bit faster than the sound waves from the basketball get to your ears, right? But you say, “Well, here it’s nearby, it’s not that big of a difference.” But now, let the person dribbling the basketball walk away from you while still dribbling. And what you see is your brain corrects for the fact that it takes time for the sound waves to reach your ears so that even though they’re moving away from you, even though the difference in time between when the light gets you, when the sound gets to you, gets bigger and bigger as they walk away, your brain knows that, and your brain corrects for it, and you still perceive the basketball hitting the ground and making the sound at the same time. Until they get a certain distance away. When the person gets a certain distance away, your brain will give up. Your brain will stop trying to synchronize the visual and auditory inputs that it gets, and you will see the basketball hit the ground at a different time than you hear it.

0:54:23 SC: Because now is not the now you perceive. The moment you live in, as a conscious creature, is not quite now; it’s a few milliseconds in the past. And at the same time, you are constantly anticipating the future. I don’t mean like, “What am I gonna have for dinner tonight?” or “Should I go to graduate school?”, or something like that. I mean, again, milliseconds into the future, your brain anticipates where your body is going to be, what it’s going to be doing. There’s a theory of motor control that says that if you have your hand on the table and you want to lift it up, the way that you do it is your brain tricks itself into thinking that it’s already up, and then it tries to bring its trick perception into alignment with its actual sensory inputs, and therefore, it lifts it up. So what you’re doing is you have an image in your brain of what your body is doing that anticipates the future and constantly tries to adjust to bring your vision of the future into alignment with its inputs. There is a constant give and take between you, the vision of what is happening now that you are constructing in your brain, and the changing environment that you’re in.

0:55:37 SC: So, even though there’s a much longer and more complicated incompletely understood story to be told here, this is why we have the impression of flowing through time, because even though to an eternalist, what exists are these different versions of yourself at different discrete moments of time, every one of them carries an image of the immediate past and the immediate future, and they’re sort of rolling through that succession of moments. A person at one moment of time has with them a little bit of the past and a little bit of the future in the form of images in their brain, and those are constantly changing, and it’s that kind of surfing that set of impressions that gives us the feeling that time flows around us.

0:56:20 SC: And there’s a very similar story to be told about making choices and having free will. We know things about the past, to an eternalist, not because the past is different from the future. We know things about the past we don’t know about the future ’cause we have records, we have fossils, and we have books, and we have photographs, and whatever. We have memories. To an eternalist, there’s no deep metaphysical difference between the past and future; we just have more access to the past. And that’s because of the arrow of time and entropy, and again, I encourage you to check out the Biggest Ideas videos, both the video about time and also the video about entropy, we talk about why we seem to think there is such a big difference between the past and future, even if there isn’t, to an eternalist. And likewise, very glancingly, we talk about why we think we have the ability to make choices, or the ability to affect the future, because we have incomplete information, we are not Laplace’s demon, but we have more information about the past than about the future.

0:57:22 SC: So, all of this sort of flowing through time gives us the impression that we can influence the future. I can make a choice right now that has an impact downstream in the future, but nobody thinks they can make a choice, no one in their right mind, thinks they can make a choice now that affects the past. And again, that’s completely compatible with eternalism and impersonal laws of physics, but it’s worth showing how that compatibility arises. So, that’s why, according to the laws of physics, we’re not surprised or even sort of… We roll our eyes when people talk about traveling to the future. That’s not what we mean, okay? When we talk about time travel, what we care about is traveling to the past. So, can we do that? And so, so far, with the laws of physics I’ve talked about, either Newtonian classical mechanics where space and time are both absolute, or with special relativity where the speed of light is a limit, the answer is very simple: No. You cannot travel to the past, in either Newton mechanics or special relativity. If either one of those theories had been correct, then travel to the past would just not be possible.

0:58:36 SC: Now, nevertheless, they wrote stories about it in the 1800s before we knew any better, when we still thought that Newtonian mechanics was possible. And so, you could go back and read those stories and ask, “How did it happen?” And the answer is basically magic. None of those stores had any detailed theory of why you could travel to the past using a time machine of some sort. You just sort of got in your steampunk sled and lights flashed and smoke was emitted, and then you were there, either in the future or the past or whatever. Okay? So it was a work of imagination, but it was not something that actually had a grounding in scientific understanding in any way whatsoever. Now, general relativity comes along. It comes along in circa 1915, and Einstein now says, “Well, I think that space-time is important. I was wrong, Professor Minkowski. Space-time is a big deal. In fact, energy and mass and all those things affect space-time: They bend it, they warp it. And we appreciate those bending and warpings as gravity, as the reason why the Earth goes around the Sun, et cetera.” And that’s going to change things a lot when it comes to time travel.

0:59:54 SC: Let me note parenthetically here that you see what’s happening in our discussion of what we mean by time travel is that number one, we’ve never seen time travel. We’ve never experienced it, we don’t have any empirical evidence of what it’s like. Number two, we don’t know the once-and-for-all-final laws of physics. Okay? So, what we’re forced to do is make all sorts of conditional statements. We say, “Well, if Newtonian mechanics had been right, it would be like this; if special relativity have been right, it would be like that; if general relativity, et cetera.” And now, soon, we’re gonna bring in quantum mechanics to the game and it’s gonna change things again. But the fact is, we don’t know. Okay? So, whenever you hear anyone pontificating about time travel and saying, “Well, it would have to work this way,” you don’t need to listen to them, ’cause we don’t know how it would work. As far as we know, it’s never happened, time travel. In fact, if I were to bet, it’s not going to happen. My simple bet is that time travel is just not possible in the real world. But we don’t know for sure, so what we’re doing is we’re imagining different possible ways the laws physics could turn out. Some of those ways might be very, very different from what we’re used to, and so, we don’t know what time travel would be like.

1:01:08 SC: But general relativity at least lets us talk about what time travel could be like in the context of a well-formed physical theory. General relativity says that space-time is not fixed and rigid, that it’s not just given to us once and for all, that it changes over time, if you wanna put it that way. But more generally, general relativity says space-time is dynamical and a little bit unpredictable. We can at least imagine different kinds of space-times. It’s not fixed by just saying there is space-time; you have to say more than that.

1:01:43 SC: So in fact, there’s a very simple way to imagine building a time machine. So what do you mean, in general relativity, by a time machine? Well, the rule that we had from special relativity was that we would have to travel slower than the speed of light. Let’s imagine that we are not ourselves photons or other massless particles. We are made of a mass of particles, so I wanna think of a real human being. Real human beings always move more slowly than the speed of light, and the technical term we attached to that was “We move in a time-like trajectory.” So we move slower than the speed of light, that means we move time-like, because in a very real sense, we’re moving more through time than through space. In the image of that diagram, we imagined drawing where time was on the vertical axis and space was horizontal. If you’re not moving at all, you’re still moving through time, you’re aging toward the future one second per second, if you’re not moving through space at all. If you move through space as fast as you can, if the beam of light is at 45 degrees, if the beam of light is equally moving through space and time, then you’re always at an angle with respect to the vertical less than 45 degrees. You are always, if you’re moving slower than the speed of light, moving more in the time direction than in the space direction. So we say you are moving on a time-like trajectory.

1:03:02 SC: And if special relativity had been true, then time-like trajectories have a very simple feature, namely that they begin in the past and they end in the future. [chuckle] That’s all they can ever do, they can’t loop in on themselves, they cannot reconnect. You can… In space, you can draw a circle. You can draw a closed curve in space. But in space-time, you could not draw a time-like curve that is closed in on itself, that loops in on itself as a circle. You can draw a curve through space-time that is a loop, but it would be time-like in some places, space-like in others. That would be a necessary feature in special relativity.

1:03:44 SC: What general relativity lets you imagine doing is having closed time-like curves: Time-like curves that are everywhere time-like. You’re always moving locally slower than the speed of light, but yet the global structure of space-time is such that you go on this curve, this trajectory through the four-dimensional universe, and you’re traveling slower than the speed of light, slower, slower, slower, and yet, you come back to exactly the point in both time and space where you left. Okay? That is a closed time-like curve or just a CTC, sometimes closed time-like loop or closed time-like line, CTL, but closed time-like curves is the most common label for these kinds of things. This is what cannot exist in special relativity.

1:04:29 SC: General relativity lets you imagine. So, I’m not gonna say the general activity allows for it, and the reason why is because the phrase “general relativity,” by itself, does not quite fix a physical theory. For those of you who know a little bit of general relativity, it’s saying that the curvature of space-time is influenced by stuff, by matter and energy and so forth. So, to have a complete theory of the world, you need to not only give me general relativity, but also a theory of the stuff, what is the stuff that makes up matter and energy and causes space and time to curve. You need that. So the reason why I can’t tell you, once and for all, whether general relativity allows time travel and closed time-like curves is because it depends on the stuff that is in the universe pushing around space-time. But I can say that general relativity allows us to imagine closed time-like curves.

1:05:24 SC: Here is a very simple example: Imagine that we did not live in an expanding universe, okay? Imagine that there was almost nothing in the universe except like maybe one galaxy with us in it. And outside our galaxy, there was nothing. Literally nothing else. So it was just flat, empty space-time outside of our galaxy, and imagine that time itself was a cycle. So imagine there was some moment, call it T=0, and 100 billion years in the future, the stuff that is in the universe reaches exactly the same condition that it had at T=0 zero, then it’s as if, and perhaps it literally is, as if you’d take the universe at 100 billion years and you identify it with the universe at time zero. So it’s like just taking a piece of paper, taking the top of it, the bottom of it, and looping them together to make a cylinder. So, space-time could be a cylinder, just like you could draw a curve on that piece of paper that always moved toward the top and yet met itself at the bottom, ’cause the whole thing became a cylinder.

1:06:30 SC: Time could be like a cylinder in general relativity. In fact, that’s even true without any stuff in the universe. Forget the galaxy, forget you. In fact, it’s easier to imagine that there’s nothing in the universe. Empty space with nothing in it, but space and time itself, could be identified from one moment of time to another with some interval in between where things could be different, and that would be a universe where every point in space-time lived on a set of closed time-like curves, namely curves that just started where they were, went to the future, came back and ended up back where they were. That’s a simple example of a time machine and general relativity. You can just basically fold the universe in on itself to make a cylinder.

1:07:13 SC: And once you do that, well, you’ve opened a large can of worms, [chuckle] a can of both physical and metaphysical worms, like if you imagine a version of this kind of universe where you could… Where you did exist, there was people in it, and maybe it wasn’t 100 billion years between the start and end, maybe it was 10 years. So, could you meet yourself from 10 years ago in that universe? Or I guess more worrisome to a physicist, we usually think of the way that we do physics as saying, “I can have some initial conditions for my billiard balls or my oscillators or my quantum fields, I can have any initial conditions I want, and then I tell you how the system evolves toward the future using laws of physics, whether it’s Newton’s law, F=ma, or Schrödinger’s equation, or whatever.”

1:08:03 SC: And again, in the usual way of doing things, it would not be the case that a complicated physical system would ever come back to exactly where it started. So, what if it fails to match? What if I say, “Well, okay, 100 billion years from now, the universe is gonna wrap in on itself?” That is a pre-condition on what is going to happen in the universe now, not just what will happen 100 billion years from now, because what’s happening now must be compatible with the idea that everything will be back where it started in exactly 100 billion years. Huh, that’s a worry. [chuckle] What are you gonna do about it? Alright. Put aside that worry for right now, so forget about these issues that arise if this can happen, let’s just think about space-time, let’s just think about general relativity. That’s a trivial example that we gave you, of the cylinder universe where time closes in on itself, and you might say, “Well, I can easily avoid that by saying the universe is not like that. The universe is not wrapped in on itself,” but then there has been, ever since since Einstein came up with general relativity, there was, for a long time, a little bit of a side light of people inventing solutions to Einstein’s equation in general relativity that predicted the existence of closed time-like curves.

1:09:22 SC: The cylinder universe example that I gave you is a little bit artificial, it’s just a global identification of two different moments of time, and who’s to say that happens? That’s not something you predict by pushing things around. It’s like God had to do it or something like that, or it was built into the universe from the start, but it wouldn’t naturally arise. So, there’s a question, can you make a time machine in some way? Can you dynamically push stuff around in the universe so as to bring closed time-like curves into existence, if they weren’t there already? And this has a long history. There’s a famous example from Kurt Gödel, who was a buddy of Einstein’s and famous for his incompleteness theorems, about the impossibility of having a sufficiently powerful number theory or other formal system that could prove all true statements. There were statements which either were provable and false, which would be bad for your theory; or unprovable and true, which means your theory is incomplete in its ability to prove things. But Gödel also… Again, he was friends with Einstein, he knew about general relativity, he was an expert in it, actually, and he proposed a solution to Einstein’s equation which was sort of a cosmological solution, it was universe filled with matter everywhere.

1:10:43 SC: But with the property, I have no idea how he came up with this, but with the property that the matter had angular momentum. So unlike our universe that has matter scattered everywhere, but on average, galaxies are rotating in one direction, one place, another direction somewhere else, there’s no overall orientation, Gödel imagined that there was matter in the universe with a net angular momentum everywhere, and he solved Einstein’s equation with this kind of condition put in by hand, and he found a solution that had closed time-like curves in it, cosmologically. And interestingly, he cared about this, he wasn’t just taking the piss, he wasn’t just having a laugh with it. Kip Thorne, who will… His name will appear again very soon, but Kip Thorne is my colleague at Caltech, one of probably the world’s expert on time travel and general relativity, and he was also a podcast guest, you can listen to our discussion about time travel and Interstellar and things like that, in the discussion with Kip Thorne, but he also, many years ago, wrote a textbook in general relativity. And when he was writing it, along with John Wheeler and Charles Misner, they actually talked that Gödel was a lie.

1:11:57 SC: In fact, when they started coming up with this idea for the book and they visited him in his office at the Institute for Advanced Study, and they talked to him and they had… I don’t know exactly what they were interested in, but what Gödel cared about, what Gödel has a question for them, was, have observations in cosmology progressed to the point where we can say whether or not the universe has an net angular momentum or not. Is the universe spinning overall, ’cause he kind of… He held out some hope that his weird cosmological solution will be relevant to the real world. But in some sense, the Gödel universe bears a family resemblance to the artificial universe where we just identify one moment of time or another. In some sense, the closed time-like curves are infinitely big, or they wrap around the universe the whole way. That’s the thing to say. They’re not infinitely big, but they’re everywhere, and they wrap all throughout the universe. So you could say, again, “Well, maybe the universe just isn’t that way. As a matter of fact, even though I can imagine the solution and write down the equations.”

1:12:58 SC: There was another solution that was proposed by Frank Tipler, which was a cylinder, and this is not a cylinder in time. So this is not a cylinder where I take one moment of time and identify it with another one. He’s thinking of literally a cylinder of matter, and this is a cylinder, cylindrical source of matter and energy that is infinitely long. ‘Cause this is what physicists can do, we can imagine unrealistic things. And furthermore, Tipler’s cylinder is spinning, spinning very fast. So, he has a small, thin, dense cylinder of matter that is infinitely long and rapidly spinning, so he saw… And again, I don’t know what inspired people to think of these things, but he solved Einstein’s equation for that kind of source. Remember, Einstein’s equation relies on having some source of matter and energy, so Tipler solved it, and what he found is that there are closed time-like curves as you get close to the cylinder. If you go… I forget whether it’s along with… I think against the sense of rotation of the cylinder, you travel in such a way that the space-time is just so curved there that you can travel in your rocket ship and you can end up arriving before you left, meeting yourself as you started your journey. But again, you could say, “Well, I don’t know. An infinitely long cylinder? Eh. I don’t think I’m gonna find any of those lying around.”

1:14:19 SC: The lesson that I wanna get here is that in all of these examples, what would it be like to travel backward in time? And the answer is, you would hop in a space ship and travel through space. In general relativity, in the presence of closed time-like curves, time machines are not like a flying phone booth that you hop into and you pop into existence, you disappear, and then teleport somewhere other in time. That’s not how it would work. Time travel in the presence of closed time-like curves is like space travel: You hop in a rocket ship and you point it along the right trajectory through space and through space-time, and you arrive before you left.

1:15:01 SC: This is the idea that just wasn’t there back in the 1800s. It’s there now, but still, people who write TV shows or movies or books, they like the magic version, they like the disappearing version. Sometimes what I use as another analogy is, imagine that there are a bunch of sentient trees who were trees, they were not ents, they cannot walk around, they’ve never traveled through space. They’re rooted to the ground, but they’re smart and they can talk to each other, and they like to imagine what it would be like to travel through space. And the only thing they can imagine is you would just sort of disappear at one location and reappear somewhere else. The idea of actually traveling through all the points in between never occurs to them. The respectable way to travel through time in general relativity does not involve appearing and disappearing; it involves traveling through all the points in between, but wrapping space in on itself in such a dramatic way that the trajectory you go on closes in on itself.

1:16:00 SC: However, all these examples that I’ve still given you, the Gödel universe, the cylinder universe, these still sort of require the whole universe to conspire in some way to make a time machine. So, we still could ask: Can we build the time machine in our garage? According to the rules of general relativity, are there things we can do, and our garage might be very big and very advanced, but it’s still finite in size. In other words, let’s put it this way: Could we imagine a universe which, to the past of some moment, had no closed time-like curves, and in a local region of space, we manipulate matter and energy and space-time in such a way as to bring closed time-like curves into existence through our actions, and therefore, build a time machine? That’s the real question that is sort of what could an arbitrarily advanced civilization do, is the way that it’s sometimes put. And the reason why this became a hot topic in physics briefly in the late ’80s, early ’90s, actually, the way I heard the story goes back to Carl Sagan, ’cause he was working on his novel Contact, and he had his hero, Ellie Arroway, fall into a black hole and gets spit out somewhere else in the universe. And Sagan was smart enough to know that’s probably not really how black holes work, but he was a planetary scientist, he was not a theoretical physicist, so he didn’t really know for sure how black holes work.

1:17:26 SC: So he talked to his friend, Kip Thorne, about how black holes work because Thorne is an expert on black holes, and Kip explained, “No, that’s not what you want. You don’t want a black hole, which would destroy someone; you want a wormhole, you want… ” ‘Cause wormholes were invented… Not invented, but they were invented by Einstein. Einstein, Podolsky, and Rosen… Sorry, Einstein and Rosen invented wormholes, and then the name “wormhole” was invented by John Wheeler, who was Kip Thorne’s PhD thesis advisor. So Kip Thorne knew what a wormhole was. It’s not a black hole where you’re sucked in and can’t leave. It is a tube, if you want, it’s a connection between two regions of space where you can travel in, if you like, they call it the throat of the wormhole, is in between, and the two mouths of the wormhole, or the two ends. So it’s like a shortcut through space-time. And usually, when you draw a wormhole, it kind of is drawn like a worm’s hole in the ground. There’s a whole that gets dug into the ground and then it comes up somewhere else. There’s a better way to think of it more realistically, because we have this image of if we were inside a wormhole, it would look like we’re in some subway tunnel or something like that, which is not quite right.

1:18:38 SC: The way that a wormhole should be thought of it is just imagine taking two spheres in space. Just imagine something feasible, like a sphere a meter across in one region of space, and another sphere, a meter across in another region of space. And I don’t mean like a sphere made of steel or dirt or anything; just imagine a region of space spherical in shape. And imagine, again, this is all in your imagination, removing the region of space interior to that sphere, to both of these spheres, and instead, identifying the sphere in one region with the sphere in the other one. So what I mean by that is, if I put my hand into one sphere, it comes out the other one. Okay? That’s a wormhole. That’s a wormhole whose throat is of zero size. A wormhole is just a region of space-time which connects two regions of space-time, the outside of which seem to be far away. So it’s a shortcut, if you like, through space time. So I take these two spheres, identify them, something that travels into one sphere pops out the other one instantly. There’s no subway ride, there’s no glowing lights or anything like that; it’s just curved space-time in a very particular way. Okay? That’s the way to think about a wormhole. And what Kip Thorne said was, “That’s what you want. A wormhole is a shortcut through space-time, and that’s what you want.” And that’s what Sagan did, and he wrote it into his novel, made it into a movie, Jodi Foster, the whole bit, okay.

1:20:08 SC: But you know, look, Kip Thorne is no dummy. He knows physics. [chuckle] He knows the bit of physics that we’ve already talked about, namely that according to relativity, moving faster than the speed of light is just as good as moving into the past, right? If you can travel faster than the speed of light, then from someone’s point of view, you’re traveling into the past. So, what Thorne realized is that if you really could… It got him thinking. Sagan’s question got him thinking about how wormholes would work. People have talked about them, his advisor had talked about them, but here it is, it’s like the 1980s, and he starts thinking about them personally in a careful way for the first time. And he realizes, from the point of view of someone outside the wormhole, someone who uses the wormhole for space travel is moving faster than the speed of light. So from someone’s point of view, someone could use that wormhole to go into the past. And he and his students figure out elaborate systems of multiple wormholes where you could sort of go into one and then go into the other one, and you could make a closed time-like curve. You could go back, you could go around through space-time by traveling through the wormholes, and you could get back before you left. Okay?

1:21:24 SC: Now, in fact, they later worked it down to just a single wormhole, and this is a little bit elaborate, but it’s worth explaining ’cause it’s just so cool. So, imagine one wormhole. Imagine we make a wormhole, don’t ask me how we make it, but we have these two spherical regions of space, the mouths of the wormhole, and you go in one, you instantly come out the other one, okay? And imagine that somehow, we can manipulate the mouths of the wormhole. We can basically put a tractor beam on and move one end of the wormhole around independently from the other one. So, this is the point, that there remains zero distance if you travel through the wormhole. You don’t actually traverse any distance going from one sphere to the other one, but from the point of view of someone outside, the two mouths of the wormhole could be very close, or they could be very far away. And so what Thorne and his friends say is, imagine that we move them, but we start them right next to each other so they’re very close, and we move one of them far away, and then we move it back. Okay?

1:22:25 SC: And they know the other one just stays constant, the other one stays put. This little thing that we just did, one mouth of the wormhole stays put, the other one moves out, let’s say close to the speed of light and then comes back, that should remind you of the twin paradox. If you put a clock on one wormhole and on the other one, the clock on the wormhole that stayed the same might know it reads an hour has passed. Well, let’s say this. Yeah, let’s say two hours have passed on the wormhole that stayed the same, on the mouth of the wormhole that stayed put, whereas the other one that went out and came back, its clock only reads one hour. Okay? So initially the two clocks, again, from the point of view of someone outside who’s watching all of these shenanigans, there’s two clocks, they both say noon, and then two hours passed from the point of view of the wormhole that stayed stationary, so its clock now says 2:00 PM, but the wormhole that went out and came back, its clock just as 1:00 PM. So they’re now out of sync by an hour.

1:23:28 SC: And you say, “Alright, that’s fine. Good special relativity, twin paradox. I get it.” But here’s the twist: When you look through the wormhole, you see what’s on the other side. You don’t see flashing lights, it’s not a subway, you see whatever is on the other side. It’s like a window, it’s like, you know, a telescope or something. You’re seeing through a view portal in space-time. And let’s imagine that our clocks are so arranged that you can see the clock on the other side, you can see the other wormhole’s clock, the other mouth of the wormhole’s clock, by looking through either sphere. So, when you’re moving, when the one wormhole is moving, it’s going out and coming back, what would I see if all along, I was looking through that wormhole at the stationary clock? Well, from the point of view of looking through the wormhole, nothing’s moving. There is still zero distance between the two mouths of the worm hole from the point of view of through the wormhole as opposed to outside. Outside the wormhole, the wormhole mouths are moving apart and then back together, but from looking through the wormhole, there’s always no change in distance whatsoever.

1:24:40 SC: And so you don’t see the other clock moving; you see it stationary. And therefore what you see is that clock ticking at one second per second, just like your clock. And that sounds paradoxical, because you say that, “Well, if I’m outside and I look at both clocks, one does a little twin paradox motion and goes forward one hour in time; one just days stationary and goes forward two hours, so now they’re out of sync,” but if, I instead of looking them from the outside, look through the wormhole, to borrow a phrase, they’re in sync. They both read the same time. So, once the wormhole that went out on a journey comes back, it says 1:00 PM, its friend that stayed behind says 2:00 PM, but when we look through the wormhole from the one that went out and came back to the other direction, we still see it saying 1:00 PM, ’cause it still has to say the same thing as the clock that was moving out and came back.

1:25:37 SC: And what that means is, I hope you followed this, I hope you bought everything I just said, what it means is if you go through the wormhole yourself from starting in the mouth that went out on its journey and came back and its clock says 1:00 PM, you come out the other wormhole not just in a different location in space, but also at a different moment in time compared to the point of view of the external observer. Since you are looking at the clock on the other side of the wormhole and it says 1:00 PM, you come out at 1:00 PM from the point of view of that wormhole mouth. So you have moved into the past from the point of view of the external observer. What the external observer sees is at 2:00 PM, you entered the wormhole, and at 1:00 PM, you exited. You exited before you left. And then you could hang around and there could be another copy of you that said hi to the copy of itself that went through the wormhole. An honest-to-goodness closed time-like curve that you made in a local region of space; you didn’t just put it into the universe from the start.

1:26:43 SC: Wow, that was a big… [chuckle] That was a big realization that they had, like, “Ohm my goodness, we can do this in a way that seems pretty straightforward.” Now, having said that, let’s back up and take some reality pills here. I haven’t seen any wormholes lying around recently. We are very unclear about whether or not wormholes actually exist in the real world. In fact, we’re pretty confident that no macroscopic wormholes do exist in the real world. There’s no reason to think that they’re out there waiting to be found. In fact, it’s worse than that. If you didn’t try… If you didn’t have a vested interest, if you didn’t really want wormhole to exist, and someone said, “Well, could you find configurations of curved space-time out there in the universe that had the form of a wormhole?”, you would think about it for a moment, and you would say, “No, I don’t think so.” And the reason why is because if you just somehow make a wormhole… Now, by the way, you can’t. In classical general relativity, there’s a theorem that is much like the theorems that say if you have a black hole, there will always be a singularity of the center, right? Singularity theorems. So in general relativity, classical general relativity, there’s a theorem that says if you try to change the topology of space-time, you will also make a singularity.

1:28:02 SC: Now, it doesn’t say you can’t do it, there are singularities in the universe, but the thought is if you try to bend and rip space-time so badly that you made a wormhole, you would almost always end up just making a black hole instead, and the whole thing would just collapse inside a black hole. So, when Thorne and his friends wrote these papers, they say, “Well, maybe there are quantum fluctuations of space-time at really tiny Planc-scale sizes, and we could somehow seize a quantum wormhole and nurse it to be bigger and grow it up to microscopic sizes.” But here’s the problem: Imagine that wormhole model that we invented, where there’s just two spheres that are identified, and I said that if you put your hand in on one wormhole, it comes out the other side of the other one. But now imagine you send in two particles. So you send them, they’re both oriented perpendicularly to the sphere, so they’re gonna hit this sphere at 90 degree angles. So, what that means is the trajectories that the two particles have to be slightly pointed toward each other. Two trajectories pointing towards the center of the earth, or perpendicular to the surface of the earth, will be at an angle where they’re coming toward each other very gently.

1:29:14 SC: But when they pop out the other side, when they come out on the other side of the wormhole, now they’re coming perpendicularly to the sphere so now they’re moving away from each other. They were initially moving toward each other, they go through the wormhole, and they’re now moving away. So, the kind of curvature of space-time that is involved with a wormhole takes particles that were moving toward each other and deflect them away from each other. So it’s kind of the opposite of what gravity usually does it. Gravity usually bends things toward each other, that you have two particles moving on a straight line, you put some gravitational mass below them that will attract them and cause them to move together. So the way we think about this conceptually is ordinarily, gravity only ever works to bring particles together. Now, there’s a footnote there with the cosmological constant and vacuum energy, but let’s not go there, that’s a different story. It’s all completely consistent with what I’m saying here. Gravity usually is attractive. But the wormhole is repulsive. It takes particles that were coming together and pushes them apart. So what it’s equivalent to, and this is not just figurative equivalence, you can go through the equations, you require negative energies to make wormholes happen and to make them stay open.

1:30:34 SC: So again, if you didn’t care about wormholes, if someone just said, “Well, alright, start with a wormhole, what happens?”, what usually happens is the wormhole just collapses before you can actually get from one end of it to the other, before you can actually go in one mouth of the wormhole and pop out the other one. So we say that with reasonable conditions on the energy of the universe, like actual sources of energy or positive energy, not negative energy, you could not make a traversable wormhole.

1:31:04 SC: Again, this is not a theorem, this is not something that is 100% proven true, because there are places with quantum field theory where maybe you can get some negative energies and there’s other things you can do that are fancier and so forth, but the general impression is that making wormholes and keeping them open is hard, maybe impossible. We don’t know enough about the fundamental laws of physics to say for sure. And then even if you had one, even you could keep it open, you would still ask questions about, “What do you mean, manipulate it? What do you mean, take one end of the wormhole and move it out at the speed of light and bring it back? How do I do that?” Okay? You can try to answer these questions, but it’s not at all obvious that your answers make sense. So, it’s a wonderful, thought-provoking experiment, thought experiment. It makes you think very hard about what general relativity is capable of, but it also makes you worry that you’re really granting yourself an enormous amount of control over space-time that maybe you don’t actually have in the real world.

1:32:01 SC: So because of that, let me just take a little detour into something that doesn’t always get mentioned when people talk about time travel, but it’s personally meaningful to me. It’s one of the first physics papers I ever wrote, or was the co-author on, was about time travel and closed time-like curves. But it was not about wormholes; it was about cosmic strings. At approximately the same time when Kip Thorne and others were thinking about wormholes, Richard Gott at Princeton published a paper pointing out that you could find an exact solution to Einstein’s theory of general relativity that was similar in spirit to Frank Tipler’s spinning cylinder, but it seemed a little more physical. And what Gott had was a cosmic string. So a cosmic string is not just a cylinder, but it’s a very, very particular type of object that can appear in quantum field theories that has both a density and a pressure and it’s sort of an infinitely long, in this idealization, an infinitely long straight string of energy, okay?

1:33:01 SC: And one of the nice things about cosmic strings is that you can solve Einstein’s equations exactly for them. If you have a single cosmic string just sitting there in the universe, there’s a fascinating thing that happens. If you’re standing next to it, you feel no gravitational attraction. Even though it has an enormous amount of energy, there is no force of gravity from the cosmic string toward you. What there is is a global effect on the geometry of the universe. What happens is… It’s actually… The point is that the actual energy and pressure inside the cosmic string has the property that there is no rest frame for the cosmic string. If you travel in the direction of the string, where the direction of the string is pointing, you cannot measure your velocity with respect to it. It’s kind of like the cosmological constant, the cosmological constant, dark energy, it’s an energy and empty space that exists everywhere, but it doesn’t have a rest frame. You can’t measure your speed with respect to it. So a cosmic string, likewise, you can travel toward the string or away from it, but if you travel along it in the same direction that it’s stretching, you cannot measure your velocity with respect it. All the velocities are the same.

1:34:15 SC: And what that means is all of the physics of the infinity long straight cosmic string is happening in the plane perpendicular to the string. There is no information that you get by moving up and down the string. Everything is in that plane that is perpendicular to and includes the cosmic string. So, it’s a model of, or an inspiration for, three-dimensional space-time. Gravity. So ordinarily, when we think about the world, we say, it’s four dimensional space-time, three dimensions of space, one dimension of time. Imagine what life was like in a three-dimensional space-time. So, space is two-dimensional, Flatland, right, except it’s not perfectly flat. You have energy, little particles, in this two-dimensional space, and they can cause a gravitational impact on the world around them. And the gravitational impact on the world around them is to cut out an angle, to turn a flat space-time to kind of like a come. So if you imagine a piece of paper and that’s two-dimensional Flatland space-time space, time is still time, so you put a dot representing a particle, and you say, “What is the gravitational field of that particle?”, the answer is, take scissors, cut out an angle from the edge of the paper to the dot, so the dot is now the vertex of a cone, you identify the opposite sides of the little wedge that you just cut out.

1:35:37 SC: So this is a weird thing about the geometry of space-time. The cone looks curved. If you see a cone, there’s sort of a curvature there, but that’s just an artifact of how you embedded it in three-dimensional space. If you unfold the cone so that it’s just a flat piece of paper with a deficit angle removed, you can see that it’s completely flat, there is no gravitational force. Those gravitational forces come from the curvature of space-time.

1:36:01 SC: Okay. So, that’s not a time machine; that’s just the gravitational field of the cosmic string, which, again, back in the ’80s and ’90s, people actually thought a lot about cosmic strings as potential sources of structure in the universe. Cosmic strings are easy to make in the early universe, and they could cause gravitational ripples that could give rise to galaxies and things like that. Those real-world cosmic strings would not be infinitely straight, and therefore, they’re not the same as twin particles in two plus one dimensions, but it’s a similar physical motivation for it. So what Richard Gott did is say, “Well, okay. Instead of just one cosmic string, I could get the exact solution for two cosmic strings moving with respect to each other, which is exactly the same as saying two point particles in a three-dimensional space-time moving past each other. I just orient their deficit angles, intersect with each other or with their trajectories, and I can solve all the equations exactly.” So, what he’s done by having… Let’s forget about the cosmic strings; let’s imagine we’re in two plus one dimensional space-time, Flatland with little dots in it and deficit angles.

1:37:14 SC: What he’s done is given the system some angular momentum. It’s sort of similar in spirit to Tipler’s rotating cylinder, but nothing’s actually rotating, two little particles are moving past each other. And what Gott showed is that, very similar to Tipler, if the particles move past each other fast enough and close enough, when they’re right near each other, you can zip around a circle and form a closed time-like curve. You can travel backward in time. Okay.

1:37:41 SC: So who cares? [chuckle] This seems almost more unrealistic than wormholes. It’s not more unrealistic than wormholes, because unlike wormholes, we know physically that cosmic strings are constructible in theory, if not in practice, but they wouldn’t be infinitely long and perfectly straight, so it’s still an idealization. But what it is, it’s an idealization that lets you solve the equations exactly. This is the great thing. All these talk about wormholes passing by each other and blah, blah, blah, blah, we’re doing a lot of hand-waving in all of these papers, and there are also equations that are very carefully solved, but there’s no exact solution to Einstein’s equation for a wormhole that starts not making a time machine and then making one; you just sort of assert that it’s conceivable.

1:38:28 SC: But in this toy Flatland example, where you have particles moving by each other fast enough to create a closed time-like curve, maybe you have a hope of solving the equations exactly, and asking yourself, could you start with particles that are stationary or not moving at all, or even just slowly moving, and accelerate them? Could you build a time machine, albeit in the two plus one dimensional universe, could you build a time machine that is an exact solution to Einstein’s general theory of relativity, where the time machine did not start in the beginning of the universe but was created by the motions of the particles? That’s a sensible question you can ask. And this is the question that my collaborators and I asked, this is with Edward Farhi, Alan Guth, and Ken Olum, we said, “Well, how do you accelerate a particle?” Well, we invented a complicated way that a single particle could blow up. [chuckle] Basically, one particle could decay into two particles moving fast back-to-back and just energy conservation, is enough to tell you how fast they could possibly move. And then you can do the work, you know, you’re a highly-paid theoretical physicist, so you solve the equations for the metric on space-time with this particular configuration.

1:39:43 SC: So you start, in your thought experiment, with two particles in two plus one dimensional space that are not moving, then you let both of them explode, so they both have two little offspring particles, two little children, that go back-to-back. And you have two of the children zoom right close to each other, and that’s exactly what Richard Gott said would make you a time machine. Okay?

1:40:08 SC: So, as long as the particles are heavy enough and moving fast enough, that kind of setup sounds like you should be able to build a time machine starting from a universe where everything was stationary, where there was no time machine, where there are no closed time-like curves. But what we did was, when we actually sat down and worked through the math, this is one of the times when it’s useful to work through the math ’cause your intuition is not quite up to the task. Remember, the way that we think about the gravitational field of a single-point particle in two plus one dimensions is start with a piece of paper and we cut out an angle and then we identify the sides to make a cone. So, we asked ourselves, we checked, how much deficit angle would you need, how much energy would the particles need to have, in order to have their little offspring particles move fast enough to make a time machine?

1:41:02 SC: And what we found was, when you added up the deficit angles of all the particles, you always got a number greater than two pi. Two pi radians, I.e., 360 degrees. So, if you think about it starting from a point on a piece of paper and you cut out an angle, you can’t cut out an angle more than 360 degrees from a piece of paper. There’s only so much angle in a piece of paper starting from the middle, there’s only 360 degrees there. What we’re saying is, what we found, is kind of like in cosmological solutions to general relativity, there are open universes and closed universes. Open universes are ones that go out spatially forever in all directions; closed universes are ones that close in on themselves to make a compact-sized space. So what we proved is that in an open universe, you will never have enough energy to make a time machine. And we didn’t put it in, we didn’t cheat, it’s just general relativity forced you into that conclusion, which I thought was just enormously neat. And we even came with a very, very clever way of proving that using anti-de Sitter space and some complicated geometry, but it was a lot of fun to think about, although not much practical application.

1:42:18 SC: And we also goofed. We didn’t goof in any of our detailed calculations, but we goofed in our and guess ’cause we guessed that even though there is not enough energy in an open universe to make a time machine, in a closed universe, the total deficit angle in a closed universe, again, little geometry fact here for you, the deficit angle of a closed universe adds up to four pi. So you can think about that, if you think about a cube, for example, and you think there’s eight vertices on a cube, each one of them has a deficit angle of 90 degrees, you can go through the math, it adds up to four pi. 90 degrees is pi over two.

1:42:57 SC: So, we said in our first draft of our paper, we showed that you can’t do this in an open universe, but it seems like you can probably do it in a closed universe. That’s worth thinking about. In a closed universe, you do have enough energy. And it was actually Gerard ‘t Hooft, who is a very famous physicist, Nobel Prize winner, who showed that the electroweak quantum field theory is re-normalizable, did a whole bunch of other good things. He became interested in this problem, and showed through… Or he argued, it’s not quite a proof, I would say, but he put forward a very convincing argument, that it’s true that in an open universe, you don’t have enough energy to make a time machine; in a closed universe, you do. But what ‘t Hooft showed is that in a closed universe, you don’t have enough time to make a time machine, [chuckle] and you’re like, “What in the world… What does that even mean, you don’t even have time to make a time machine?”

1:43:52 SC: In an open universe… The thing about open universes in two plus one dimensions is there’s an infinite amount of space. It just goes on forever. But a closed universe has an area, you would say a volume in three dimensions, but now we just have two-dimensional space, so it has an area, and guess what? As soon as you do our trick, have a couple of particles, let them explode into sub-particles, offspring particles, the volume of space, the area of your two-dimensional surface, begins to shrink. It’s like the universe is collapsing. And what ‘t Hooft showed is that it always shrinks to zero size before you make a time machine. So, to me, that was just another amazing unpredictable fact, like, somehow, the thing about the time machine or the thing about the cosmic strings or point particles in two plus one dimensions, it’s very non-general, it’s obviously extremely specific, extremely delicate, and unrealistic, in some sense, but it’s a toy model, it’s a spherical cow, you can solve all the equations exactly. And we got counter-intuitive results from solving the equations, namely, you cannot build a time machine in either an open universe or a closed universe. In an open universe, there’s not enough energy; in a closed universe, there’s not enough time. So that’s good to know. It’s indicative, it’s suggestive, that somehow, general relativity doesn’t want you to make time machines.

1:45:22 SC: And around that time, Stephen Hawking also wrote a paper called The Chronology Protection Conjecture, where he used high-powered differential geometry from his old days as proving singularity theorems and black holes, and he proved a theorem that basically said, and this is back in the real world, three plus one dimensions, that if you started without closed time-like curves and you put ordinary reasonable restrictions on what matter you have, no negative energies or things like that, if you did things dynamically in a compact region of space in an attempt to make closed time-like curves, you would always make a singularity. And the implication is that rather than building a time machine, everything just collapses to a black hole. That’s not a theorem. There’s something called the cosmic censorship conjecture, which says that when you have singularities, they’re always inside black holes, but it’s not quite a theorem, and maybe you could get around it. But again, the suggestion is there, that when you try to make closed time-like curves, even with wormholes or whatever, you will instead collapse everything to a black hole.

1:46:33 SC: And this was also backed up by some of the more explicit calculations people did with wormholes. When they actually tried to look at the behavior of quantum field theory in the background of these wormholes moving around, what you find is that as you try to make a closed time-like curve, as you try to manipulate the one wormhole mouth to the point where there is a path that takes you to the past, even though you’re going forward in time, the energy density on that path just from quantum fluctuations tends to diverge, tends to become infinitely big. And I say “tends to” because they tried to get around it, and there were arguments, and I’m not even sure that they ever decided whether it was a theorem one way or the other, but over and over again, from very different angles, we got the impression that the real world wanted to prevent you from making time machines. So this is why, when I say general relativity allows you to imagine making time machines, I also say, but at the end of the day, I suspect that in the real world, time travel is just not possible.

1:47:37 SC: And even if all of this discussion about building time machines in general relativity is a little bit deflationary, is a little bit… It’s harder than you think, even though it’s conceivable, it’s not ruling out, once and for all, the idea that you can do it. So we still have the ability to ask if you did do it, if you did have a time machine, if there were closed time-like curves generated by the curvature of space time, what would it be like? What would be… What would the consequences be? How would time travel work in that kind of context? We have a much better framework for thinking about the physics and the philosophy of time travel than we would in the magic world of HG Wells or whatever.

1:48:20 SC: So for example, there’s two things that we instantly get, two conclusions, from this. One is that if you do have a world where you make a time machine by building closed time-like curves, by pushing things around and having their gravitational fields… Sorry, by the way, I should say, if you wanted to have a time machine that you could actually travel through, even if you forgot about the fact that probably you would just make a black hole, wormholes require negative energies, all of that, you’re thinking here about manipulating amounts of energy that are truly astrophysical in size. You’re thinking about solar-sized mass concentrations packed into a very small region of space. So there’s yet another engineering reason why it’s hard, but okay. Forgetting about that.

1:49:13 SC: One lesson is, you can’t travel into the past, into the time before you made the closed time-like curves. So let’s say that somehow you could conjure a wormhole, let’s say, out of the quantum foam, and then manipulate it so that it created closed time-like curves. You couldn’t use that to travel to moments before you did that. You could keep the wormhole around, maybe, arguably, and then toward the future, you would always be able to come back to that moment when you made it. Even if there was only a one-hour shift when you went through the wormhole, you could just keep going into it. If you were a year in the future, you could just go through that wormhole many, many, many, many times, and come all the way back a year into the past. But you couldn’t go into the past before you actually built the time machine, as it were, in the first place. So, sometimes people, including Stephen Hawking, like to make a joke that we have evidence against the possibility of building time machines because we’ve not been invaded by tourists from the future. But that’s not actually a valid argument. It’s a good joke, but it’s not a valid argument, because maybe we haven’t yet built the time machine, and then once we do, we can go back to that moment, but not to any moments before it.

1:50:26 SC: The other thing, of course, which is perfectly obvious, is that what a time machine would look like is it would look like a rocket ship. It would not look like a sled or a telephone box; it would look like a space ship that could move across the right trajectory through space-time. So, time machines are kind of down-to-earth, in that sense. It’s the existence of the closed time-like curve that is exotic, not the transportation method we use to get around there.

1:50:52 SC: Okay. Having all that in our bag of tricks, what can we say about the traditional issues that are raised by the possibility of time travel? You know what they are, right? You could travel into the past and kill your grandfather before he met your grandmother, and then you wouldn’t be born. This is, in fact, this is called the grandfather paradox. Not quite sure why it’s always your grandfather who’s the target of this, someone has issues there, but this is a paradox. What if you went back and kill baby Hitler? That’s another popular target. For one thing, is it morally right to kill baby Hitler? We know grown-up Hitler did terrible things but baby Hitler hadn’t done anything yet. It’s sort of a pre-cognition, pre-crime kind of thing. Maybe baby Hitler could have just been treated better and things would turned out very, very differently.

1:51:40 SC: But putting aside those moral dilemmas, what does it mean to go into the past and kill Hitler, whether as a baby or not? We have memories of Hitler existing, we have photographs. Changing the past in that way seems to be, if not completely paradoxical, then at least apparently paradoxical in the following sense: There’s a tension between the fact that we know and have records of certain things having happened in the past, but as we discussed, we have a feeling personally, since we’re not Laplace’s demon, of an ability to make choices. So if you can go into the past and make the choice to kill Hitler and therefore change the course of history, how is that compatible with the fact that we know that Hitler really existed? That’s the essence of all the different grandfather time loop paradoxes that we face.

1:52:43 SC: After Kip Thorne and his friends wrote about wormholes, Joe Polchinski, who was another physicist, sort of formalized these worries into a more tractable toy model paradox, the billiard ball Paradox. He pointed out that if you had a wormhole that had a closed time-like curve generated by it, that you could throw a billiard ball, you could imagine, anyway, throwing a billiard ball into the wormhole so that it came out the other way, and if you aimed it exactly right, the wormhole would shoot the billiard ball out into the past in such a way that it would deflect the original billiard ball from ever entering the wormhole. So basically, the billiard ball is killing its own grandfather, you throw a billion ball into the closed time-like curve and it goes to the past and prevents itself from entering the closed time-like curve, so what happens? Okay, that’s the billiard ball, that’s Polchinski’s billiard ball Paradox. And Thorne and his friends took this very seriously, and again, we’re not… Let’s just stick to the laws of physics as we currently know them, in fact, less than as we currently know them. Let’s think of classical physics.

1:53:51 SC: By “classical,” I don’t mean obeying Newton’s Laws, relativity counts as classical, but what I mean is not quantum mechanical, okay? There’s only one world here, we’re not doing many-worlds quantum mechanics or anything like that, but also, we’re trying our best to generalize the laws of physics a little bit. After all, part of classical mechanics is Maxwell’s… I said Maxwell’s demon. Laplace’s demon. The idea that you could, in principle, know the exact state of the universe at one moment in time, and from that, predict the past and the future. The thing about the grandfather paradox or the billiard ball paradox is, this is calling into question the idea, the motivating principle, behind Laplace’s demon, the idea that you can think of the history of the world starting from some initial values and integrating forward in time and backward in time. Because that makes perfect sense, when time is only one-dimensional and never loops back on itself. It makes sense to say in ordinary Newtonian space-time or special relativity, if I know the state of the universe at one time, I can use the laws of physics to extend that state into the past and the future.

1:55:10 SC: But when time can, in principle, loop back on itself, what does it mean to have an initial value problem? This goes back to the worry that we had, about the cylindrical and time universe, where we just identify one moment of time with another moment of time by hand, doesn’t that seem to impose some global, weird, invisible constraint on what the initial values for matter inside such a universe can be? Because they need to be such that the matter returns to exactly its same condition 100 billion years later, or whatever that time period was later. So, in some sense, and maybe you shouldn’t be surprised, we’ve opened Pandora’s box and scared away Laplace’s demon. We’ve said that we’re changing the rules of the game to allow for these closed time-like curves, and so maybe we shouldn’t be surprised that some of the old rules and ways we had of doing physics, of setting up initial value problems, aren’t going to work anymore.

1:56:09 SC: Now, that it doesn’t mean that we throw away the laws of physics entirely, or that we throw away the idea that there should be laws of physics. What we should do is ask, are there different kinds of laws of physics that work in the presence of closed time-like curves, and are also reduced through the laws of physics that we know and love when there are not closed time-like curves? And I think… I actually haven’t kept up on this as much as I did some number of years ago, when I first started thinking about time machines, but my impression is that we’re not completely sure about what the answer to that question is. So if you ask the question in the most ambitious form, are there rigidly expressible, perfectly clear, and unambiguous laws of physics that both completely avoid any possible paradoxes but give unique answers in the presence of closed time-like curves, and reduce to ordinary laws of physics when they are not closed time-like curves. I don’t think that there are, or I don’t think that we know whether there are such generalizations or not.

1:57:14 SC: What there are… What Thorne and others proposed, including Igor Novikov, who is one of their collaborators, something called the Novikov Consistency Condition, which is, even though you can imagine that in, let’s say Polchinski’s billiard ball paradox that the billiard ball prevents itself from entering the wormhole, there is a different trajectory, which is self-consistent. So even though this one trajectory you started imagining prevented itself from happening is therefore not consistent, you could argue that there are other trajectories that are consistent, so there is a trajectory where the billiard ball goes in and knocks itself into exactly the right position to enter the wormhole at the right time. And you can’t necessarily know what these trajectories are by starting with initial conditions and just letting the laws of physics chug forward in time, but there’s some global way of stating them.

1:58:10 SC: Again, my impression is, as far as the existence of these consistent solutions is concerned, that there is good evidence that they exist, there’s a very real worry that there’s more than one of them, that they’re not unique, that given… It’s unclear what information you have to give me to pin down exactly what the behavior has to be. But it seems, from the work that has been done, that you could always find some consistent solutions to the behavior of matter in the presence of closed time-like curves. So at least, it opens up the possibility that even though there’s not the sort of Laplacian way of doing physics, starting from the conditions right now and just chugging forward in time, there might be a more global way of looking at the entire space-time and saying, “Here are the allowed conceivable trajectories, and here are not.” And after all, that wouldn’t be the weirdest thing in the world.

1:59:04 SC: Even in ordinary physics, even forget about closed time-like curves. We know that there’s something called the principle of least action, which for those of you who don’t know, again, I recommend checking out my videos on the Biggest Ideas in the Universe, there’s one on force, energy in action, and what we talk about there is the fact that there’s a way of formulating the laws of physics that says, starting from some initial point and ending in some final point, consider all the possible trajectories that a system can take between them, and there’s a quantity that we can write down called the action, it’s an integral of kinetic energy minus potential energy, but who cares? It’s a quantity. And the real physical motions of actual systems in the universe are the minimum values of that action.

1:59:50 SC: And that’s a global quantity. It requires knowing the whole shebang from the beginning of the system to the end. It’s not this, you tell me what’s going on now, and I chug forward in time; I calculated quantity knowing the whole system over time. And maybe you could argue that that’s a sensible way to think, from this eternalist perspective, from the block universe perspective, where we don’t think of time as something that literally propels the universe from moment to moment. Time is just a coordinate on what exists, which is a four-dimensional space-time. Maybe the laws of physics should be intrinsically four-dimensional from the beginning. So I think that’s a fascinating possibility. I don’t know what the state of the art is about that, I’m just telling you what my most recent impressions are about it.

2:00:42 SC: The nice thing about that is that idea of a consistency condition, the idea that when you have closed time-like curves, you can’t just start anywhere you want and chug forward in time, but there are still consistent stories to be told in this background, might translate over to literal stories, from toy model physics scenarios into movies and novels and TV shows. So the idea of this consistency condition in a more narrative context is, what happens, what gets in the way, if you try to go back and kill baby Hitler? I think the answer was succinctly summed up on Lost, the TV show, of all places, they had time travel in season five or whatever it was. And they were worried about… [chuckle] It was kind of funny, since Lost was not always worried about making sense, but when it came to time travel, they were sort of weirdly insistent on making sense. And so they had a motto, which is, “Whatever happened happened.” And what that means is, if you know that World War II happened in this world, in their fake time travel world, you could imagine traveling back to World War II, but you cannot imagine killing baby Hitler. You could imagine trying, but you know you will fail because baby Hitler was not killed.

2:02:07 SC: The same thing is true with preventing JFK from being shot, or preventing yourself from doing that embarrassing thing at the senior prom, whatever it is, whatever way you want to change the past. You can imagine, in other words, visiting the past, but if you do, you always did. You were always there in the past, your older self is always part of the pre-existing past. And it’s what you might call a single, consistent world approach to time travel. There’s a block universe, but time does not simply flow forward, sometimes time can loop in on itself, but at every point in the block universe, at every set of events, at every location in space and time, something happened. And there was only one thing that happened, this is the single consistent world approach. Whatever happened happened.

2:02:58 SC: There are other movies and stories that try to get this right, and are a little bit more detailed than Lost, I can mention two of my favorites, which are 12 Monkeys, it’s a consistent time travel story in this single consistent world sense. There’s an even more elaborate one called Time Crimes. 12 Monkeys tries to trick you into thinking that they’re changing the past, but then you find out that they’re not really… Sorry. Spoiler alert. Time Crimes is this elaborate time loop kind of thing where a person interacts with themselves.

2:03:31 SC: The master of this, of course, was Robert Heinlein, who wrote several stories involving time travel and where he tried to sort of make time loops… He wasn’t worried about wormholes or consistent general relativity, he had the magic disappearing-reappearing in time idea, but it was completely consistent. So a person could interact with themselves at different points along their personal timeline, but in ways which always, at the end of the story, you realized only one consistent thing set… A set of things happened. The most intricate and impressive version of this was his story, All You Zombies, which I only really recently realized, like this week, ’cause I was looking up time travel movies, was made into a movie with Ethan Hawke. They changed the title, so it’s called Predestination, is an Ethan hawk movie based on Heinlein’s All You Zombies story. It’s not a super great movie. I mean, Hawke is good, but the story does not lend itself to becoming cinematical very easily. And to my enormous frustration, at the end of the movie, I’m not giving anything away here, but at the end of the movie, they hint that maybe you can change the past, which is like destroying the entire point of the story. The whole point of the story was everything was perfectly consistent in a single consistent world, and they hint maybe that’s not true. It’s kind of defeating the purpose, but…

2:04:54 SC: But it’s interesting, because storytellers, just when they are given the toy to play with, of time travel, they really, really want to change the past. It’s something deeply rooted in human psychology, that if you tell people you can visit the past, there’s this enormous desire to fix it, to change it, somehow. So if you try to tell them, “Well, no. There’s laws of physics, you’re not allowed to do that.” They don’t wanna hear it, and in fact, they will tell you that all the interesting stories are where you change the past. Which is weird, because there are many, many interesting stories called mystery novels or detective stories where you’re not changing the past, because you can’t visit it, ’cause there is no time travel, but you’re nevertheless telling an interesting story because you are discovering the past. I think there are many, many interesting time travel stories to be told where you visit the past and don’t change it, but you learn something about it. So, for any budding screenwriters out there or novelists or short story writers, still plenty of room to write interesting time travel stories that do not necessarily violate the single consistent world approach.

2:06:06 SC: But you understand why it is tempting, because remember, we had this idea that you are not Laplace’s demon personally, you do not have all that information, you are a tiny, very, very incomplete, imperfect set of atoms and molecules with incomplete knowledge about the world, and that in your view, and then as an emergent, effective higher level macroscopic thing in the manifest image of the world, you think that the past is fixed. Right? You think the past is there, I can’t change it. But you also think that you can change the future, that you have volition, that you have free will, that you can make a choice, and that the causal ramifications of your choices propagate forward into the future. And this is… I think this is fascinating. This is why time travel stories puzzle us or intrigue us at the same time, it’s because in a time travel story, the past of the universe gets mixed in with the future of you, with the future of the people who travel into the past. And if you have this conviction, that because you are this finite person, you’re not really embedded in this eternalist ideology, you think that the past is fixed and unchangeable, but the future is affectable, then when your personal future, like what are you gonna do next, becomes part of the past, it’s just really hard to resist the conclusion that I can change the past. Like, “What stops me from going and killing baby Hitler?”

2:07:40 SC: And the answer, in a single consistent universe picture is, I don’t know. I don’t know what stops you, but something will stop you. That’s what I know. I know you will be stopped. So, in fact, this is what gives a little bit of dramatic tension to these stories, as rare as they are, but the dramatic tension comes from the fact that you know not to try to change the past, because you know you will fail, but you don’t know why. You know that what happened happened, you need to work in the constraints of what knowledge you have about the past. It might be that you failed because you get killed, or you to get sick and die, or you fall off a cliff. It’s very, very dangerous to try to change the past and you know you won’t succeed, so I think that actually kind of has dramatic possibilities for it.

2:08:31 SC: I’ll give you another example of… A good example of time travel, which actually was Bill & Ted’s Excellent Adventure. We mentioned Ed Solomon and Bill and Ted at the beginning, in the original movie, there’s this famous scene where Bill and Ted need the keys to… I don’t know, a car or a door or something like that, they don’t have the keys, and they don’t have enough time to go get them, but they also know that they know about the existence of a time machine. So they figure out, “A-ha. In the future, we can go into the past, steal the keys, and leave them for ourselves behind this sign.” So they go, they look behind the sign, and there they are, there’s the keys.

2:09:13 SC: So this is a slightly different twist on it, because they’re not constrained by knowing the past; what they’re doing is by getting a favor from their future selves, they are obligating their future selves to do the thing, to go into the past, get the keys and put them there. And they say this, they mentioned this. Like Keanu Reeves, Ted, says, like, “But what if we don’t actually do it?”, and then he says, “But I guess we did do it ’cause the keys were there.” [chuckle] Or… Sorry. I guess he says, “I guess we will do it, because the keys are there.” That’s the point. You can say, “Well, what if they just get the keys and then their future selves decide not to go back and steal them?” Well, that’s not allowed by the laws of physics, their future selves or an equivalent thereof, did and will and always have been stealing the keys. It’s hard. It’s hard to sort of wrap your mind around that, but it is consistent. This is why time travel breaks our brains a little bit. The single consistent world scenarios make it hard to believe in human choices in exactly the same way.

2:10:17 SC: And by the way, again, footnote here, that is important: If it bothers you to think that there’s some non-local, global consistency rule that makes certain choices impossible and not something that you have the free will to carry out, don’t worry about that, because time travel is probably not possible, [chuckle] right? What we’re doing here is saying, if time travel were possible, what would the rules be of the game, and speculating about that.

2:10:48 SC: Okay. Now, all of you know that in the world of time travel stories, very, very few of them, hew to this logic of the single consistent world. Some of them do, good for them, but most of them want to let us change the past. And you might say, “Well, doesn’t logic prevent this? Didn’t we just give an argument that you can’t change the past ’cause whatever happened happened, it’s already there?” Well, that would be true, except, of course, as you also all know, there is to conceit that there are multiple timelines or multiple universes. So, there’s the idea that since we’re inventing things anyway and we’re not sure how to make them happen, let’s invent the idea that when we go to the past, we go to a different past than what we actually remember happening. So maybe there is a universe where we remember World War II as we remember it and we have documentary evidence for it, but let’s imagine that if we could travel to the past, we also bring into existence a whole new world, a world where we can kill baby Hitler or whatever, prevent JFK from being shot.

2:11:58 SC: And typically, this is just invented by magic. Again, there’s no physical explanation given for where these new timelines come from, hands are waved, pictures are drawn, whatever, but it’s not the laws of physics. But you also know that there is a version of the laws of physics where something kind of like this sounds like it happens, namely in quantum mechanics, especially in the many-worlds interpretation of quantum mechanics. Now, quantum mechanics, as you know, as most of you know, have heard me say, we have rules of quantum mechanics, but we don’t know the final once-and-for-all formulation of it. They’re competing what we call interpretations, they’re not really interpretations, they’re competing physical theories, but there are different theories, all of which look like quantum mechanics to us as we see it experimentally. Most of these different theories do not have multiple worlds, parallel timelines, or anything like that, but one of them, the Everett interpretation or the many-worlds interpretation does.

2:12:57 SC: Now, for those of you who, for some reason or another, have not heard me talk about this, the idea behind many-worlds interpretation is not that Hugh Everett, who invented it, sat around and said, “What if there were like a billion worlds, man, that’d be awesome!” It’s actually much, much simpler than that. There’s an equation, the Schrödinger equation, which is the equivalent of Newton’s laws of physics but for quantum mechanics. It’s the equation that says what the quantum state does, how it evolves. It’s a perfectly deterministic equation. It’s perfectly definite in what it predicts. It is not, by any stretch of the imagination, anything goes. Many-worlds interpretation of quantum mechanics does not say that whatever you wanna imagine happening is gonna happen somewhere in the multiverse. Instead, what it says is, go back to what we said before about measuring a quantum mechanical system, you can measure an electron to be spin up or spin down, you only ever see one response. You either see the electron spinning clockwise or counter-clockwise, never both. And the many-worlds interpretation says that’s because the wave function of the universe splits, and there was only one world before a world where the electron was in a superposition of clockwise and counter-clockwise, and there are two worlds after.

2:14:15 SC: So, Everett’s idea is just that that’s the whole story. That’s it. Everett’s idea is just that the Schrödinger equation, which every version of quantum mechanics uses sometimes, is the entire story. The Schrödinger equation, like it or not, predicts that there are multiple branches of the wave function of the universe, which we can interpret as multiple worlds. Other versions of quantum mechanics try to get rid of the other worlds one way or the other, by hook or by crook. So, the many-worlds interpretation of quantum mechanics is a physical theory, it’s not just hand-waving, there are very definite equations that tell you what happens. And it predicts that there are, if you like, multiple worlds, many, many different copies of reality, all of which are slightly different from each other, all of which have slightly different things happening. In some, the electron was spinning clockwise; in some, it was spinning counter-clockwise.

2:15:10 SC: So, it is just irresistibly delicious [chuckle] to think about combining the idea of the many-worlds interpretation with the idea of time travel, the idea of closed time-like curves. In other words, we can ask ourselves the question. Before, we were talking about general relativity in the classical world. Now, let’s say, what if we have closed time-like curves in general relativity, but the fundamental laws of nature are quantum? So, what if we can have multiple worlds and closed time-like curves in the same package? Does that mean that if I hop in my closed time-like curve, I can travel to the past and either enter or create a new world, a new branch of the wave function, a new universe, a new timeline, whatever you wanna call it, where things are not exactly what I remember them being in my good old-fashioned timeline? I think that the answer is we don’t know. [chuckle] I don’t think this has ever really been worked out to anyone’s complete satisfaction.

2:16:19 SC: There is a famous work by David Deutsch, who is a famous physicist, a pioneer in quantum computing, and also, a famous proponent of the many-worlds interpretation, where Deutsch looked at quantum mechanics in the presence of closed time-like curves. And I think that people know that fact. They know that David Deutsch wrote a paper about quantum mechanics in the presence of closed time-like curves, and David Deutsch is a proponent of the many-worlds interpretation, and therefore, they leap to the conclusion that David Deutsch says that I can hop in a time machine and enter a different world and change the past. Okay? But he didn’t quite say that. There’s a certain apparatus and formalism that goes along with the many-worlds. And I’m not gonna go into all the details, but branching of the wave function into multiple copies happens in certain specific ways under certain conditions when a tiny quantum system becomes entangled with the rest of the outside world. And so there’s a very well-understood procedure for branching and creating different worlds.

2:17:20 SC: Deutsch wrote a paper where he imagines evolving a quantum system in the presence of closed time-like curves, of a particular, not very realistic but easy-to-analyze variety. That’s okay. But he doesn’t… And he shows that there can be a consistency condition. He shows that it is possible to imagine quantum states in the presence of these closed time-like curves that are completely consistent. That’s what he shows, roughly speaking. He does not show that you can travel into the past and branch off a new world. There’s no discussion about decoherence, branching, entanglement with the environment, any of those things. You could talk about those things; as far as I know, no one has. I think it’s an interesting research project that I’m sort of tempted to do myself. Could you actually not only do what Deutsch did, or take what he did, and build on it by saying not only is there consistency condition, but here is how you could bring into existence extra branches of the wave function where different things happened?

2:18:24 SC: Maybe not. It’s not at all clear that the answer is yes. There are very basic questions when you open this kind of can of worms. Like if your future self travels to the past and your past self is still there, what about things like conservation of energy? Did the universe something to get more massive ’cause there’s now two copies of you? Or does a copy of you shift over one universe in every single branch? There’s N branches, and you move from branch number N to branch number N plus one, or whatever it is.

2:18:58 SC: But regardless, all of this discussion, it’s important to distinguish the actual physics paper discussion by Deutsch and others from movie discussion. What Deutsch and others have been discussing is quantum mechanics in the presence of closed time-like curves. None of it is about changing the past. So here is another… In the spirit of thinking about closed time-like curves in general relativity and drawing some conclusions from them, even if you could sort of fulfill the fantasy of having a closed time-like curve traveling into the past and creating a new branch of the wave function, one of the implications of the many-worlds interpretation is the old branch is still there. You didn’t get rid of it. Right? Maybe you can create a new branch, maybe not, but you didn’t change, in any way, the old branch: It branched or it didn’t. And so, there is still a world, the world in which we live, in which baby Hitler grew up to be old Hitler and do a bunch of terrible things. So, you can ask yourself whether it’s sort of fulfilling the narrative purpose of traveling into the past if all you’re doing is creating a different world where things turned out differently but not changing the old world where things turned out badly at all. Okay?

2:20:16 SC: Maybe it is. We could argue back and forth, but this is why I think it would be interesting to have a better handle on how you could have branching and new world creation in the presence of closed time-like curves, so you could really talk about the moral and human implications, even if it was far outside of our actual technological capabilities to actually do this.

2:20:37 SC: So, I think that maybe that’s a little unsatisfying, that discussion, because what I’m saying is there’s a lot we don’t know. But sometimes that’s what is happening. So let me hit the finish line here by circling back to movies like Back to the Future. What we were just talking about was sort of a hypothetical multiple world theory where you literally create a new branch of the wave function, but you didn’t get rid of the old one. By the way, a footnote to that, if you do the sort of science fictiony idea that you created a branch of the wave function or you create a new world by traveling backward in time, and then the old world does disappear, so let’s imagine you’re not doing many-worlds Interpretation of quantum mechanics, let’s imagine you’re inventing some new fictional version of multiple-world theory where you go back, change the timeline to do something else, and then the old timeline disappears, then you are clearly history’s greatest monster, right? Because you are erasing from existence billions of people who had their memories. Even in a bad timeline where the Holocaust happened, there’s still other happy things that happened, and you would be erasing them from history. Is that really something good that you wanna do? Is that really something that is a moral good overall?

2:21:55 SC: Of course, all time travel stories, or many time travel stories, have this lesson of hubris built in, like you try to change the past and you make things worse. I think that’s just storytelling laziness. But as a real question, it’s not at all clear what the moral value is of creating new timelines and destroying old ones. Happily, that’s not what the many-worlds interpretation says you can do. But also, most time travel stories are not in the context of the many-worlds interpretation; they just make things up. And this is where we get back to Back to the Future. Why is Back to the Future bullshit as far as time travel is concerned? Again, it’s a great movie, it works narratively really, really well, but logically, it does strain one’s credulity. So, one way, in many ways, but one way, just to make it a simple straightforward example, Marty McFly, played by Michael J. Fox, goes back into the past, he starts in the ’80s, goes back to the ’50s, and he carries with him a photograph of him with his siblings, and he messes with his parents in the past in various ways.

2:22:58 SC: And what happens is as he changes their lives in the past, the photograph that he’s carrying with him from the 1980s begins to change. It is clear that the things that he is doing in the ’50s to the lives of his parents are changing their futures in such a way so that they did not have kids. And so therefore, this photograph of Marty and his brother and his sister, his siblings begin to gradually disappear from the photograph. This makes no sense. At least at face value, this just drives you crazy, if you try to make any sense of it. Just let me… Of all the many, many objections one could raise, let me just raise the most obvious one: Why is it happening now? If Marty changes the past so that his parents, let’s say, don’t have any kids at all, then where did he come from? Why did he have a photograph at all? Why did the photograph change and not him? And why is it happening now as he’s doing this, in real time, as we’re watching the movie? None of this makes any sense whatsoever.

2:24:04 SC: There’s another example, which is actually more to the point. In a more recent movie, Looper. If you’ve ever seen Looper, it’s a great movie, again, terrible time travel logic, in some sense, but a wonderful narrative movie, a wonderful story. Joseph Gordon-Levitt and Bruce Willis Play one time traveler in different moments in their lives. So the idea behind Looper is we’re in the present day, not our present, the future to us, but the present day of the movie, and there are people whose job it is to assassinate people from the future. So basically, there’s a future where there’s a government or something that is trying to get some people out of the way, and the way they do it is they send into the past and these people in our present day, from the point of view movie, kill them. And that includes themselves. So what you buy into as a bargain, if you’re one of these assassins called loopers, is that you will eventually be sent back and you will be killed, but along the way, you get a lot of money and rich and famous or whatever.

2:25:07 SC: So, inevitably, there’s gonna be… I don’t know, it’s a bad system. I don’t know whoever set up the system, but the people who are sent back who were loopers, who are assassins, they know what the deal is, so of course, they’re gonna try to escape. So, a minor character named Seth, in the beginning of the movie, he’s a looper and he shows up to kill someone being sent back, and it is in fact his older self, his future self, old Seth. So old Seth comes and is supposed to be killed by young Seth. Young Seth just can’t do it. Old Seth sweet-talks him into, “Don’t kill me,” and he escapes. But then so old Seth has escaped, that’s against the rules, and so the syndicate or whatever, the powers that be, capture young Seth and start torturing him. They start snipping off his fingers with garden shears. So he’s losing fingers. And what you see is it’s exactly equivalent to the Back to the Future thing, old Seth, he’s trying to escape, he’s trying to run away, in real time, as we’re watching the movie, he’s looking at his hand, and every time he looks at it, it has fewer fingers on it. Because at that time, as the movie goes, young Seth is being tortured and his fingers are being snipped off.

2:26:22 SC: Hmm. [chuckle] How does that make sense? So you can see very, very clearly why that doesn’t make sense. If young Seth was tortured and had his fingers snipped off, why did old Seth ever have those fingers? Why did he have a full set of fingers on his hand, when he came back? His younger self had been tortured, right? This is not a single consistent world in any sense. So the traditional response to this, and certainly, the response that I’ve given, is that’s just bad time travel. [chuckle] That is just not logical in any way. But here we are, we’re giving ourselves the homework of being a responsible consultant on a movie like this. The movie already exists, so they don’t need consultants, but the question is, as imaginative scientists, can we invent a set of laws of physics, can we invent a way the world works, that could make sense of movies like this, where what the viewers see is changes that seem to propagate in weird ways between different versions of reality?

2:27:32 SC: None of these are even simply reconcilable just by saying, “Oh, there’s a new timeline,” because if there’s a new timeline, if Marty McFly goes to the past and creates a new timeline, then he just either brings the picture back with him or doesn’t. And if the picture is with him, the picture shouldn’t be changing as he does things in real time in that timeline; the picture is a picture of a different world from a different timeline. So we need to imagine inventing a new version of the laws of physics where that thing that he is doing in the 1950s leads to changes that propagate into a different world and then is noticeable by him. Or in the Looper example, what is being done to young Seth, his fingers are being cut off, only now is being noticeable by old Seth, even though he has no memory of not having fingers for the last 30 years or whatever.

2:28:25 SC: Can we do it? I think we can. I would not be building up to this. I think that if we really try hard, we can make sense of this. But there’s a rule in physics or whatever that the more surprising and weird the phenomenon is, the more you’re gonna have to work to introduce some weird elements into your theory to explain it. That’s not surprising, right? So we’re gonna need some leaps of faith here, but I think I can come up with the scheme that involves four ingredients on the basis of which we can actually make sense of Back to the Future, Looper, and other similar movies.

2:29:03 SC: So one ingredient is, we clearly need multiple parallel worlds. So if you’re gonna make sense of this, you have young Seth and there is young Seth who we see being tortured, his fingers are being snipped off, but there’s also a world in which young Seth does not have his fingers chopped off, because that young Seth needs to grow up into the old Seth that we see, who has his fingers when the movie starts. So at the very least, we need a world with Seth with fingers and the Seth where fingers gets… Where Seth’s fingers get chopped off. Or we need a world where Marty McFly was born with his siblings and that photograph was taken of them, there’s another world in which his parents either do not meet or do not have those siblings or the photograph was not taken, et cetera. We need all those worlds. That’s the least to ask.

2:29:52 SC: The second ingredient is these worlds are not completely separate. The worlds can interact in complicated, ongoing ways. So it’s not just that the wave function of the universe branches and now you have two separate worlds like you do in the usual many-worlds interpretation of quantum mechanics; there needs to be ways that the different worlds can sort of continuously share things back and forth from each other at the right time. So, when you literally see the photograph beginning to fade, or when you literally see Seth’s fingers disappearing from his hand, what’s happening is the reality of one world is being moved into another world. You might think that that’s a lot to ask, but again, we’re trying to figure out the minimal set of ingredients to make sense of this craziness, and we’re gonna have to be asking a lot. It’s only gonna get worse from here. So, ingredient one is multiple parallel worlds; ingredient number two is they interact with each other in constantly, ongoing complicated ways.

2:30:54 SC: Ingredient number three, and here, the buys become rather costly: You need to imagine that minds can move and evolve independently from, or at least in ways not directly tied to, their physical bodies. So you have to be a mind-body dualist to explain this. How do we know that, or what makes us insist on that? Well, think of old Seth looking down at his hand, seeing his fingers disappearing. When he sees them disappearing, he’s surprised, he’s upset, he’s like, “Uh, I guess my young self is now having his fingers chopped off,” right? But he remembers having his fingers. They’re disappearing now, but Seth’s mind is from a world where the fingers were there the whole time. So what gets knitted together, this is ingredient number three in our list of four ingredients, there needs to be a knitting together of different things going on in different worlds that allows us to take the minds and memories of experience from one world and put them in the bodies of people from other worlds, so, by the end of the narrative in Looper, the body of Seth that had the fingers chopped off is together with the mind of the Seth that did not have the fingers chopped off, at least not originally. So, good. Mind-body dualism, Rene Descartes would be very happy with this. Plenty of other modern philosophers would also be happy, although a minority.

2:32:26 SC: Okay. The fourth ingredient, which is maybe the biggest and hardest to make sense of, is the following: Remember that with both the images and the pictures dissolving and in the fingers dissolving, one question was, why now? What is it… It’s actually worse in Back to the Future than in Looper. In Looper, the fingers are disappearing on old Seth at the same time in that world when they’re being chopped off of young Seth, so that kind of makes some sense. But in Back to the Future, Marty McFly is back in the ’50s doing things, and gradually, the photograph is changing. And in both cases, whether it’s fingers or photograph, why did they wait until this moment to do that changing? How do they know that it’s supposed to be at this time when things are happening? So especially when you have, as you always do in these movies, the focus of the movie jumps back and forth in time. There’s scenes from the future and scenes from the past, et cetera, but that’s also a clue to how we solve it.

2:33:28 SC: So ingredient number four is, there needs to be another time dimension of some sort. So, what you need in addition to many, many worlds that have both physical reality and mental reality in each of them, each one of these worlds has a time coordinate in the sense of this universal time that just tells you how the universe is evolving from moment to moment, but there’s a separate idea of time, which we might call narrative time. It is the time as seen by the audience of the movie, or as experienced by the person reading the book, if it’s a time travel story. And this narrative time is what stitches reality together. I know it’s a big leap, it’s very different than the usual laws of physics, but this is what we need. It’s roughly reminiscent of hidden variable theories of quantum mechanics. If you know about hidden variable theories of quantum mechanics, they also have the Schrödinger equation, and there’s a wave function and it branches, but there are variables, hidden variables, that sort of say, “This branch is the one that counts as real.”

2:34:36 SC: So what I’m saying here is that there needs to be an extra ingredient which takes all of these different worlds, all these different minds, all these different bodies, all these different experiences, and stitches them together to make a single coherent reality that evolves according to this narrative time. And it’s that reality that says that, “Oh, yeah, young Seth having his fingers chopped off is in some sense at the same time as old Seth realizing that he no longer has fingers,” and stuff like that.

2:35:07 SC: Now, you might say, “Well, where does that narrative time come from? Who decides what it is?” And there, I don’t know. I can imagine two different ways of making it work. One way is the most direct way: There’s an audience. That’s what actually makes it all makes sense in the movies. When you watch Back to the Future or Looper or whatever, you can get puzzled and confused and scratch your head, but overall, they’re good, sensible stories. You know that when the image on Marty’s photograph starts to become altered, you understand his emotional reaction to it. He realizes that the world that he left behind, even though it’s in the future, is becoming threatened. The emotional resonance is perfectly clear. So, there must be some possible logic behind these stories if they make sense to us and affect us.

2:36:04 SC: So, maybe it’s something like the simulation argument. The simulation argument, if you heard my recent podcast with Nick Bostrom, says that all of what we think of as reality is actually just a computer simulation being run by a much more advanced civilization potentially obeying very different laws of physics. So maybe you could imagine that this narrative time element that stitches reality together is literally smarter people, aliens, that play the role of editors or writers or whatever it is. They create a story by stitching together different things that happened in different universes. Or God, if you wanna call it God. Or the devil. [chuckle] Whoever. Some supernatural force. That’s fine. It’s kind of a cop-out. It’s kind of like too cheap. It’s sort of cheapening the experience that we live in. It’s not the laws of physics; it’s some external force that is constructing our reality, okay, but it does hang together.

2:37:00 SC: The other possibility, which I’m not sure at all whether it’s… It’s one of these half-baked ideas, which you would have to ask, could you make it into a fully-baked idea, maybe there is some minimization procedure. Remember the principle of least action. The principal of least action says you can derive the laws of physics for ordinary physical bodies, the laws of motion, by saying that there is some quantity that you get by integrating over all the motion that is minimized in real-world happenings. Maybe there is some quantity that is minimized or extremized or whatever by these particularly narrative coherent stories.

2:37:41 SC: So stories like Back to the Future or Looper are not coherent by ordinary laws of physics, but they make sense as stories. So, when old Seth sees his fingers disappearing, he is upset, and you get it. You get why he’s upset. Even though he’s lived for the last several decades with those fingers, now he has lost them, and he’s upset, and you get that. So if the fingers disappeared but he suddenly switched to having no memory of having those fingers, then there’s no emotional resonance there at all, it’s not a new timeline; it’s just a different timeline. And that’s less interesting, so maybe there is some narrative version of the principle of least action. Maybe there is some quantity we could imagine calculating that makes the story makes sense when you stitch together all the different multiple worlds including closed time-like curves in this particular way.

2:38:40 SC: Or maybe not. I don’t know. [chuckle] It’s not something that I’ve sat down and written and written anything about, I’m not even sure it could be done. But my point is the following: That it’s fun to think about time travel stories, even the ones that don’t make sense. I stitched together, I came up with this scheme involving, okay, multiple parallel worlds, they can interact with each other, minds and bodies are independent from each other, and there’s a narrative time that stitches them all together, as my best attempt to make sense of what happens in movies like Back to the Future and Looper and elsewhere.

2:39:19 SC: I think it’s a useful exercise, if only philosophically or for story-telling purposes. Maybe not for physics purposes, but making sense of things is what we do as intellectually curious creatures that try to make sense of the world. Time travel is a wonderfully interesting provocation to our urge to make sense of the world, because it takes things that we take for granted and brings them into question. It raises questions of fate, our ability to change the past, the importance of the past, as well as just curiosity about what things would be like if things had gone very, very different. It makes us think, and it makes us think in a novel way, that’s why time travel is fun, that’s why the stories are so irresistible. Time travel stories make us think about who we are and about how we live in the real world, not just the fake world. And that kind of inspiration is always a good thing.

[music][/accordion-item][/accordion]

7 thoughts on “124 | Solo: How Time Travel Could and Should Work”

  1. I really enjoyed this episode. It had a good mix of scifi and physics, all told in an educational and methodical manner. I was long, and I enjoyed it all the way through.

    In my frame of reference (as an observer of a subset of your episodes) it was different, and I would love to hear more like it. In the past, or in the future.

  2. An interesting overview of time travel possibilities. But it seems you missed one nuance. You discussed going back and time and changing the future from that point as causing a branching to the future. But why not take a multiverse model in which going back in time is also going to a parallel universe which was the same as the one you left up till your arrival from the future. So instead of branching, all possible universes are in parallel and your machine just changes which one you find yourself in.

  3. Maria Fátima Pereira

    Excelente!!!

    Um pouco complexo, mas, entendivel (relendo algumas transcrições), considerando também, que é um ótimo comunicador.
    Uma visão muito realista.
    Um remate perfeito, justificando como nossa ânsia de dar sentido ao mundo, levantando uma série de questões.
    Obrigada, Sean Carroll

  4. My partner and I listened to this episode with great enjoyment. We thought the emphasis on the theory-dependence of any answer to the issue of time-travel was especially refreshing.
    I know recommendations must be annoying at a certain point, but we kept waiting for you to mention the German Netflix series Dark. Since you did not, I can only assume you haven’t seen it. Given some of your own proclivities about how time travel should be portrayed, not to mention your quantum theory sympathies, I think you would find this quite a remarkable series. Independent of the science, it’s one of the best series of recent memory. But the use of time travel is also mind-stretching and fascinating. I’d encourage you (or anyone who enjoyed this episode) to check it out!

  5. Jose Castro-Mora

    The worst time travel plot of all time is in the first Superman movie. I’m wondering if as a consultant and viewing its plot as data if there exists a theory that could save it (doubt it, it’s beyond repair). I saw it as a kid and even then it made me cringe with frustration: Superman flies around the earth to make it rotate east to west, and by doing so, turns time back and reverses the effects of an earthquake.

  6. Sean, I listened to this podcast today and I found it very interesting and enjoyable. I was thinking about the Back to the Future fading picture problem and I may have one way that could have worked. Perhaps as the night wore on, Marty’s probability of success getting his parents together was decreasing. As you recall he started fading himself while on stage. I’m thinking that the current probability of success at any one time is getting applied to his current situation and the picture fades or gets stronger as a result. Just a thought. Thanks.

  7. Sean, great podcast! One logical error I think you have is at 2:10:30 when you discuss the single consistent world approach and how you know you cannot change the past. As an example you say that maybe you get killed trying to change the past – that by itself would not be consistent with the approach. After all you did live to travel to the past, so you cannot die trying to change the past. Thanks!

Comments are closed.

Scroll to Top